The Universality of the Prohibition of the Crime of Genocide, 1948-2008

AuthorCaroline Fournet
Published date01 June 2009
Date01 June 2009
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/1057567709335394
Subject MatterArticles
132
International Criminal
Justice Review
Volume 19 Number 2
June 2009 132-149
© 2009 Georgia State University
Research Foundation, Inc.
10.1177/1057567709335394
http://icjr.sagepub.com
hosted at
http://online.sagepub.com
The Universality of the
Prohibition of the Crime
of Genocide, 1948-2008
Caroline Fournet
University of Exeter, UK
The year 2008 marks the 60th anniversary of the adoption, under the auspices of the United
Nations, of the Convention for the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, a
legal instrument generally acknowledged as providing for the authoritative definition of geno-
cide. Yet, if this Convention undoubtedly carved into positive international law a widely
accepted definition of the crime, it is nonetheless remarkable that the prohibition of genocide
also finds its origins in the obscure concept of peremptory norms of international law, other-
wise referred to as jus cogens. The present article thus proposes to assess this apparent frag-
mentation of sources and ultimately attempts to evaluate the impact, value, and significance
of the Genocide Convention.
Keywords: jus cogens; prohibition of genocide; and universal jurisdiction
Since its conception, public international law has been plagued by rhetorics and
recourse to the sacralized and dark notions of natural law, divine law, and jus cogens
norms. The idea that international law knows of superior norms, no matter how compel-
ling, sits nonetheless uncomfortably with the very essence of public international law as
a law made by and for states. Indeed, peremptory norms of international law—also known
as jus cogens norms—contain within themselves the concept that international law knows
of certain nonderogable norms, forming a legal corpus to which no exception, restriction,
or limitation of any sort can be formulated. Jus cogens norms thus correspond to absolute
norms—Weil referred to them as “normes à autorité renforcée” (Weil, 1992, p. 262)—with
which states have to comply, regardless of any conventional obligation, and by imposing
a nuclear vision of international law, such norms arguably create a legal hierarchy. As a
closer look at jus cogens norms reveals their undefined status, the international normative
order finds itself confronted to an absurd situation where the peremptory norms, which
must be abided by regardless of any contractual obligation, pertain to the unknown. As
Weil further explained,
Among the charges most currently cited we will solely retain three: the difficulty, confining to
the impossibility, of identifying jus cogens norms; the risk it holds for the stability of treaties;
its essential, almost visceral, incompatibility with the international system’s structure. (Weil,
1992, p. 269)1
The very existence of jus cogens norms is undoubtedly a contentious issue, and even if
one admits that they do exist in international law, fully uncovering the veil of their obscure
Fournet / Prohibition of Genocide 133
content remains an arduous—and arguably overambitious—task. Yet, and notwithstanding
its recognition in positive international law, the crime of genocide has also—on several
occasions—been qualified as a peremptory norm of international law, and this duality of
identities necessarily prompts the twofold question of the necessity of the prohibition of
genocide as a jus cogens norm, on one hand, as well as of the utility of its embodiment in
a specific international treaty. By proposing to analyze this schizophrenia of the law of
genocide, the present article ultimately aims to contemplate whether, 60 years after its
adoption, the Genocide Convention should still be considered as a fundamental instrument
or whether it should merely be seen as a redundant and thus unnecessary text.
The Problem With Jus Cogens: Sources of International Law
Sources of public international law are usually understood, and rightly so, as being based
on state consent. Indeed, Article 38 (1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice
(ICJ), “widely recognised as the most authoritative statement as to the sources of interna-
tional law” (Shaw, 2003, p. 66), lists a series of sources that are all based on the assumption
of state consent. It accordingly refers to international conventions “expressly recognized by
the contesting states,” to international custom “as evidence of a general practice accepted
as law,” to the general principles of law “recognized by civilized nations,” and to “judicial
decisions and teachings,” which implicitly presuppose state consent, states having arguably
recognized the jurisdiction of the institution giving the judicial decision in question and
having accepted the expertise of the “most highly qualified publicists.” Jus cogens is thus
not expressly listed among the sources of international law and, while this does give cre-
dential to the theory that this category is in reality inexistent, it could nonetheless be argued
that jus cogens relates to the norm rather than to its source.
Furthermore, it could also be submitted that jus cogens norms reside within the—
admit tedly equally vague—concept of “general principles of law recognized by civilized
nations” (ICJ Statute, Article 38 [1]). Due to their alleged normative superiority, it might
indeed be unrealistic—if not dangerous—to contend that such norms could ever be encap-
sulated in a broader category, sitting outside the ambit of Article 38 and yet cohabiting with
the supposedly inferior norms listed therein. To put it differently, jus cogens norms and
“general principles of law recognized by civilized nations” might thus cover the exact same
reality. Other than locating jus cogens norms within the ambit of Article 38 (1), it must be
conceded that this reasoning is not as helpful as it could be, due to the fact that the general
principles of law are also deprived of any authoritative definition. As Professor Shaw
recalled,
Some writers regard it as an affirmation of Natural Law concepts, which are deemed to under-
lie the system of international law and constitute the method for testing the validity of the
positive (i.e., man-made) rules. Other writers, particularly positivists, treat it as a subheading
under treaty and customary law and incapable of adding anything new to international law
unless it reflects the consent of states. (Shaw, 2003, pp. 93-94)
This definitional opacity notwithstanding, the expression of civilized nations here
deserves further exploration. Indeed, leaving aside any moral understanding of the notion

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT