THE PSYCHIC LIFE OF PUNISHMENT (KANT, NIETZSCHE, FREUD)

DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(03)30009-2
Pages211-245
Date09 December 2003
Published date09 December 2003
AuthorKlaus Mladek
THE PSYCHIC LIFE OF PUNISHMENT
(KANT, NIETZSCHE, FREUD)
Klaus Mladek
ABSTRACT
This article seeks to recover and uncover the non-utilitarian excess (jouis-
sance) in crime and punishment since Kant. Jouissance is sharply contrasted
with Nietzsche’s account of ressentiment. The latter is analyzed as the
predominant sensation of our penal system which until today structures the
subjects and institutions of punishment from within. Jouissance, on the other
hand, is obscured in philosophies of punishment that attempt to account for
the will to punish but ultimately fail to cover over the excess that constitutes
penal theories and practices. Whether it is visible in Kant’s punitive fervor,
in the exploration of perversion in de Sade and E. A. Poe, in theories of
deterrence and prevention or punitive convictions in our contemporary legal
culture, Freud’s discovery of a realm beyondthe pleasures principle remains
crucial for the understanding of the motives for crime and punishment. The
essay concludes with a discussion of Nietzsche and his exploration of the
ramifications of recognizing the roleof new affects in crime and punishment.
Qu’est-ce que c’est la jouissance? Elle se r´
eduit ici `
an
ˆ
etre qu’une instance n´
egative. La
jouissance, c’est ce qui ne sert `
a rien. Je pointe l`
alar
´
eserve qu’implique le champ du droit-`
a-
la-jouissance. Le droit n’est past le devoir. Rien ne force personne `
a jouir, sauf le surmoi. Le
surmoi, c’est le imp´
eratif de la jouissance – Jouis!(Lacan, 1975, p. 10).
Evenguilt andpunishment donottell uswhat thelaw is,but leaveit ina stateof indeterminacy
equalled only by the extreme specificity of the punishment (Deleuze, 1991, pp. 82–83).
Punishment, Politics, and Culture
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society,Volume 30, 211–245
Copyright © 2004 by Elsevier Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1016/S1059-4337(03)30009-2
211
212 KLAUS MLADEK
(O)ne need only to look at our old penal codes to discover what amount of effort it takes to
breed a “people of thinkers” on earth (G 38).
PUNISHMENT AND JOUISSANCE
(KANT, NIETZSCHE, FREUD)
Our politics, our history and our fantasies are bathed in the jouissance1of law
and punishment. Surprisingly few have noticed that Nietzsche’s second treatise
in the Genealogy of Morality is predominantly about this surplus-jouissance in
the history and theory of law and punishment. The question of jouissance arises
once we become aware of the stark difference between usefulness and enjoyment,
between the officially legitimized ends and the non-theorizable surplus of punish-
ment. Lacan has traced the concept of jouissance back to its juridical etymology.
In law, it is nothing else but the legal notion of “usufruct” (ius utendi fruendi),
the right to temporarily enjoy the use of certain rights of others. In Roman law,
it is usually associated with the enjoyment of someone else’s property. Nietzsche,
on the other hand, systematically extends the legal concept of usufruct to the
enjoyment of rights over someone else’s body. Punishment for Nietzsche derives
from the contractual right to enjoy the power over another body.2However,
the legal concept of usufruct also introduces limits into jouissance, for one is
allowed to enjoy this power, but not abuse or squander it: “Precisely this is the
essence of law – to divide, to distribute, to spread out that which is jouissance
(Lacan, 1975, p. 10).
Without mentioning the term usufruct (Nießbrauch) explicitly, Nietzsche links
the notion of usufruct to the origin of debt or guilt (Schulden). “Schuld” itself has
its roots not in penal but in contract law.To guarantee the payment of the debt, the
debtor pledges to the creditor something that he possesses, “for example his body
or his wife or his freedom or even his life (...), finally even his peace in the grave”
(G 40). The creditor thus has legally established power over the debtor’s body,
rights and possessions. The creditor is “granted a certain feeling of satisfaction as
repayment and compensation – the feeling of satisfaction that comes from being
permitted to vent his power without a second thought to one who is powerless,
the carnal delight ‘de faire mal pour le plaisir de le faire,’ the enjoyment of
doing violence.” Nietzsche concludes that the idea of compensation and Schuld
originates in the establishment of a “right to cruelty” (G 41). It is important to
notice that Nietzsche is not so much interested in the means or ends of cruelty
(to enforce the validity of contracts or to deter one from breaking promises), but
rather in the “senseless” satisfaction of legally inflicting pain “without a second
thought,” for the mere pleasure of doing it. Punishing jouissance is thus to enjoy
The Psychic Life of Punishment 213
the violation of someone else’s body without guilt: to commit violent acts in the
name of law and morality. This particular constellation of usufruct reminds one of
de Sade’s enjoyment of crime as universal law – the crime as end in itself, where
the law functions solely as support for the jouissance of transgression.3
The law may distribute, domesticate or prohibit jouissance, but something
escapes from this, something that is not useful or utilitarian and which has no
reason or determined origins and neither clear means nor ends. For Nietzsche,
the good is not determined at the level of use, its “goodness” is rather decided
upon by the notion of control and power. Thus, the good of punishment does not
reside in its various goals (betterment, deterrence, etc.), but in the creation and
manifestation of power. Outside of use value and the notion of good, Nietzsche
emphasizes something radically new which could be called, with Lacan, the
jouissance use” (Lacan, 1992, p. 229):
The judgment ‘good’ does not stem from those whom ‘goodness’ is rendered! Rather it was
the ‘good’ themselves, that is the noble, powerful, higher-ranking, and high-minded who felt
and ranked themselves and their doings as good, which is to say,as of the first rank, in contrast
to everything base, low-minded, common, and vulgar. Out of this pathos of distance they
first took for themselves the right to create values, to coin names for values: what did they
care about usefulness! The viewpoint of utility is as foreign and inappropriate as possible,
especially in relation to so hot an outpouring of highest rank-ordering, rank-distinguishing
value judgments: for here feeling has arrived at an opposite of that low degree warmth
presupposed by every calculating prudence, everyassessment of utility – and not just for once,
for an hour of exception, but rather for the long run (G 10–11).
Nietzsche reveals that the domain of the good marks the birth of power,difference
and distinction. The notion of control of the goods and the creation of values
is crucial, not their use value. The contemplation of goods and uses only keeps
us in the mediocre “warmth” of pleasure but prevents us from our confrontation
with jouissance. The mere fact of exercising control and exacting punishment
is thus infinitely more important than the actual use or regulation of goods and
bodies. The “high-minded” must therefore not be concerned with defending
their goods, but with inventing them and naming their own values instead. Both
Nietzsche’s will to powerand Lacan’s jouissance are directed against the ideology
that persuades us of the link between pleasure and the good – the pleasures of
good or the good as pleasurable. Instead, a “hot” and enduring “feeling” (“not
just for once”) lies at the very heart of Nietzsche’s “will to power” (see Deleuze,
1983, p. 62). The “outpouring” of pure will is thus nothing else but the surge
of jouissance, a “feeling” and a principle so “hot” that they compel us to move
beyond the calculus of pleasure. Both will to power and jouissance recognize acts
of destruction and aggression as potentially joyful.4Accordingly, the “pathos of
distance” treats the dull warmth that flows out of the nexus of pleasure and good

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT