“FOREMOST AMONG THE PREROGATIVES OF SOVEREIGNTY”: THE POWER TO PUNISH AND THE DEATH OF COMITY IN AMERICAN CRIMINAL LAW

Published date09 December 2003
Date09 December 2003
Pages33-50
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(03)30002-X
AuthorKarl B Shoemaker
“FOREMOST AMONG THE
PREROGATIVES OF SOVEREIGNTY”:
THE POWER TO PUNISH AND THE
DEATH OF COMITY IN AMERICAN
CRIMINAL LAW
Karl B. Shoemaker
ABSTRACT
This essay explores a radical shift in how the relationshipbetween the power
to punish and sovereignty has been conceived in modern American law;
specifically focusing on the quiet death of comity as an operative principle
in the exercise of criminal jurisdiction. While this essay attends to certain
legal issues arising from historical intersections of federal, state and Indian
sovereignty in the field of criminal law,this essay is not an attempt to directly
evaluate the history of federal policies applied to Indian tribes or tribal lands.
Nor is this essay in any strict sense a legal history of federal-tribal relations,
or federal penal policy in relation to Indian tribes. Rather, I am concerned
here with a series of liminal moments in the American legal tradition in
which the power to punish came to be understood ever more one-sidedly, as
an atomizing attribute of sovereignty rather than an identifying feature of
community within a pluralistic legal framework.
Punishment, Politics, and Culture
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society,Volume 30, 33–50
Copyright © 2004 by Elsevier Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1016/S1059-4337(03)30002-X
33
34 KARL B. SHOEMAKER
INTRODUCTION
In Supreme Court jurisprudence, the power to punish has been represented both as
a centerpiece of sovereignty and as a marker for membership in distinct sovereign
communities. As the Court recently pronounced in the context of federalism, “the
power to create and enforce a criminal code” stands “foremost among the prerog-
atives of sovereignty” (Heath v.Alabama, 474 U.S. 82 (1985)). As a historical
concomitant, American law has also characterized the power to punish as closely
linked to, and limited by, the boundaries of community membership. Hence, the
power to punish not only signals a core feature of sovereignty, but also signals
the contours of a sovereign political community. In punishing, a community
distinguishes itself both as capable of “exercising its own sovereignty” (United
States v.Wheeler 435 U.S. 313 (1978)), and as capable of claiming those who
belong to it.
Not surprisingly, this understanding of sovereignty has figured prominently
in legal conflicts between Indian tribes, states, and the federal government over
matters of criminal jurisdiction. First, through a series of federal treaties, Supreme
Court decisions, and congressional legislation stretching back to the end of
the eighteenth century, the power to punish has been a basis for support of (or
challenges to) Indian sovereignty. Forexample, in early nineteenth-century cases,
several Supreme Court justices specifically treated the power to punish as a sine
qua non of sovereignty. At numerous points in those decisions, Indian tribes were
determined to possess (or lack) sovereignty based on their capacity to punish
their own members. Second, early treaties with Indian tribes were sometimes
preoccupied with the question “who could punish whom?” The possibility that
Indian tribes might exercise criminal jurisdiction over white settlers, or white
settlers over Indians, was a cause of some anxiety in the late-eighteenth and
early-nineteenth centuries. Community membership checked, at least in principle
if not always in practice, the exercise of penal power over non-members. The
power to punish at once anchored claims of sovereignty and limited the reach of
sovereign power exercised by federal, state, and tribal communities respectively.
A venerable tradition of political thought conceives the relationship between
sovereignty and the power to punish in much the same terms. After all, the word
“sovereign” – derived from the Latin verb superare (to overcome, to vanquish,
and, tellingly, to survive) – speaks already the intimate link between dominion
and sanction. Machiavelli, for instance, understood the power to punish as a
constituent element of sovereignty, and named that power necessary for the
continued survival of a healthy republic (1970). Hobbes was equally explicit,
listing the power to punish in his catalogue of “Rights” necessary for the
“Institution of a Commonwealth” (1988, p. 90).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT