“SUBJECTIVITY IS A CITIZEN”: REPRESENTATION, RECOGNITION, AND THE DECONSTRUCTION OF CIVIL RIGHTS

Published date09 April 2003
Date09 April 2003
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(02)28006-0
Pages139-188
AuthorJonathan Goldberg-Hiller
“SUBJECTIVITY IS A CITIZEN”:
REPRESENTATION, RECOGNITION,
AND THE DECONSTRUCTION
OF CIVIL RIGHTS
Jonathan Goldberg-Hiller
INTRODUCTION
The progressive limits to rights mobilization have become starkly apparent in
the past two decades. No new suspect classes have been forthcoming from the
Supreme Court since 1977 despite continued demands for legal recognition by
lesbians and gays, indigenous peoples and others interested in expanding civil
rights doctrine. Public tolerance for civil rights measures has likewise dried up.
Since the 1960s, referenda on civil rights have halted affirmativeaction programs,
limited school busing and housing discrimination protections, promoted English-
only laws, limited AIDS policies, and ended the judicial recognition of same-sex
marriage, among other issues. Nearly 80% of these referenda have had outcomes
realizingtheMadisonianfearof“majoritytyranny”1andsignalingtheNietzschean
dread of a politics of resentment (Brown, 1995, p. 214; Connolly, 1991, p. 64).
While frequently inchoate, recent debates over the extension of civil rights
protection to new groups have been framed around a persistent asymmetry.Propo-
nents of civil rights recognition have asked for rights as a hallmark of citizenship
while claiming present laws to be inadequate for their recognition and protection;
their opponents have argued that citizenship is not at stake, that new rights are
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society,Volume 28, 139–188
Copyright © 2003 by Elsevier Science Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/PII: S1059433702280060 139
140 JONATHAN GOLDBERG-HILLER
redundant if not excessive, and consequently,the identities sought to be protected
are artificial or misrepresented (Burlein, 2002; Cooper, 1998; Goldberg-Hiller,
2002; Patton, 1995; Schacter, 1997, p. 684). “Post-civil-rights era”2discourse has
thus been marked both by challenges to the tactics and rhetoric of recognition as
well as the boundaries of political bodies in which citizenship ought now inhere,
propelled as much by language and the social movements which help generate it,
as it is by broader changes in social and economic organization that have fueled
anxieties. This paper explores two recent debates over civil rights in Hawaii– one
over same-sexmarriage and the other over constitutional recognition of indigenous
rights claims – in an effort to deconstruct these newer civil rights discourses and
the way that civil rights law now comes to constitute political subjectivity.
My approach to these debates is inspired by studies of legal mobilization which
have urged us to decenter our attention from the formal character of rights to the
ways in which actors and discourses bring law into social action.3The cases I
study here ask us to also consider the ways in which law is pushed away, rights
argued to be morally and politically inappropriate for social organization. I show
that pushing rights away paradoxically may tend to recenter law through new
ideas about political sovereignty, fashioning post-liberal ideas of citizenship and
assumptions of the self.4These ideas are politically ambivalent. In some forms and
contexts, this discourse of sovereignty – the rhetoric that invokesit, the ontological
ideas that it depends upon (and which depend upon it) – has inhibited progressive
civil rights movements. In other contexts, post-civil-rights sovereignty discourse
works to sustain progressive forms of collective action. My goal in this article is
to open this discourses to criticism, to show the social constructions that underlie
claims to be naturally emergent, in order to advance our understanding of law and
enhance progressive efforts of legal mobilization.
I do this by presenting two case studies. In the case of same-sex marriage, I
show how sovereignty discourse can work to builddemocratic majorities opposed
to civil rights advances by creating stable political identities unavailing of self-
criticism in the very manner in which they resist civil rights appeals. In the case
of indigenous rights struggles, I demonstrate the ability of some proponents to
deconstruct these barriers and question the ontological certainty that surrounds
this discourse. My deconstruction is shadowed by critical international relations
scholarship which has urged that we creatively move beyondsovereignty5and the
works of Emmanual L´
evinas who rejected its ontological premises in his ethical
critique.
Ifirstsketcha theoretical approach to the discourse of sovereigntythatmodulates
these civil rights conflicts.6Sovereignty invites deconstruction, I argue, for the
pervasive assumptions about subjectivity and community that it depends upon,
and the silences that it enforces as a political and legal idiom. After presenting
Subjectivity is a Citizen 141
my two case studies, I explore implications of this deconstruction for alternative
political practice. Throughout this analysis I endeavor to show the scholarly and
practical importance of taking seriously discourses aligned against civil rights.
RECOGNITION AND ORDER
The presumption of liberal civil rights models to protect the “discrete and insular
minority”7– as individual and as faction – from the tyranny of the majority has
its genealogy in a Hobbesian imagery of sovereignty and its construction of social
ordering. Against the frightening image of a state of nature in which life devoid
of political agreement is famously solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short, Hobbes
arrays an artificial image of the self in which sovereignty is to be alienated.
For by Art is created that great LEVIATHAN called a COMMON-WEALTH, or
STATE ...which is but an Artificiall Man; though of greater stature and strength than the
Naturall, for whose protection and defence it was intended; and in which, the Soveraignty is an
Artificiall Soul, as giving life and motion to the whole body...by which the parts of this Body
Politique were at first made, set together and united, resemble that Fiat,ortheLet us make man,
pronounced by God in the Creation (Hobbes, 1968 [1651], pp. 81–82).
How well this artificial man can salve “the multiplicity of allergic egoisms which
are at war with one another and are thus together” (L´
evinas, 1991, p. 4) depends in
part on what the artificial soul of the sovereign body politic recognizes as its limits.
For one, it matters how this artificial soul problematizes8the Other, for as Shane
Phelannotes, “The trope of the body politic works powerfullytotransform contests
within society into attacks on society” (1999, p. 58). For another, the success of
the sovereign construct turns on how well the artificial languages – such as civil
rights – convey this recognition.
As many criticisms of the Hobbesian project recognize, biases abound in the
very assumptions of political sovereignty,particularly in the privileging of reason,
but also in the philosophical and political alchemy of the body politic into
ideas of identity/difference, self/other, inside/outside, History/contingency and
imminence/transcendence.9In Bryan Turner’s words,
The Hobbesian problem of order was historically based on a unitary concept of the body ....
However, the regime of political society also requires a regimen of bodies and in particular
a government of bodies which are defined by their multiplicity and diversity. The Hobbesian
problem is overtly an analysis of the proper relationship between desire and reason, or more
precisely between sexuality and instrumental rationality. This problem in turn can be restated
as the proper relationship between men as bearers of public reason and women as embodiments
of private emotion (Turner,1984, pp. 113–114).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT