MINORITY REPRESENTATION, THE SUPREME COURT, AND THE POLITICS OF DEMOCRACY

Date09 April 2003
Pages33-72
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(02)28002-3
Published date09 April 2003
AuthorYasmin A Dawood
MINORITY REPRESENTATION, THE
SUPREME COURT, AND THE POLITICS
OF DEMOCRACY
Yasmin A. Dawood
ABSTRACT
This article develops an alternative theoretical approach to the Supreme
Court’s controversial electoral redistricting decisions in Shaw v. Reno
(1993) and its progeny.Instead of relying on the traditional equal protection
interpretation, this paper argues that controversies over electoral redis-
tricting are at base disputes among competing visions of democracy. In
the Court’s recent redistricting cases, the majority and the dissent adopted
fundamentally different visions of democracy – Individualist Democracy and
Democracy as Power. In addition to elaborating these rival understandings
of democracy, this article develops the concept of Symbolic Democracy to
explain a central paradox in the Court majority’s decision: its simultaneous
denial and recognition of the relevance of racial groups in representation.
INTRODUCTION
Racial oppression in the United States has been historically tied to the exclusion of
African Americans from the polity. The quest for democratic inclusion continues
to this day, although the objectiveis no longer the attainment of the formal right to
vote. In the contemporary period, racial oppression is fundamentally based on the
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society,Volume 28, 33–72
Copyright © 2003 by Elsevier Science Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/PII: S1059433702280023 33
34 YASMINA. DAWOOD
lack of political power. Although African Americans have the ballot, they enjoy
scant legislative influence on the public policies that govern their everyday lives.
These urgent issues – voting, representation, race, power and exclusion – are at
the center of the Supreme Court’s recent adjudication of minority representation.
In the 1990s, the Supreme Court ushered in its “new jurisprudence” on minor-
ity representation with its controversial rulings in Shaw v. Reno (1993) and its
progeny.1The Court held in Shaw v. Reno (1993) that certain majority African-
American electoral districts violated the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment. In Shaw, the Court considered the constitutionality of the Twelfth
District, a majority-minority legislative district in North Carolina. What appeared
to fuel the Court’s hostility to the district was its unusual shape: it followed the
I-85 corridor for almost 160 miles until, as the lower court described it, the dis-
trict “gobble[d] in enough enclaves of black neighborhoods.” In an ironic twist,
white voters launched suit claiming that the state had created an unconstitu-
tional racial gerrymander and had violated their constitutional right to partici-
pate in a color-blind electoral process. Adding to the controversy surrounding the
Shaw case was the fact that, as a result of the Twelfth District, North Carolina
sent its first African-American representatives to Congress since Reconstruction
(Shaw v. Reno 509 U.S. 630; 1993).
The Shaw case represented a dramatic departure from the Court’s prior position
that race conscious districting would at times be required in order to protect the
ability of racial minorities to elect a candidate of their choice.2In the next case,
Miller v. Johnson (1995), the Court broadened the scope of Shaw by holding that
a redistricting plan would be found invalid if “race was the predominant factor”
motivatingthe legislature when it devised the plan (Miller v. Johnson 515 U.S. 900;
1995). The Supreme Court applied its new jurisprudence in Bush v. Vera (1996)
and Shaw v. Hunt (1996) to overturnthe constitutionality of the majority-minority
districts at issue in those cases. In all four cases, the dissenting justices rigorously
criticized the Court’s new stance on minority representation.
What is at stake in the Supreme Court’s recent adjudication of minority repre-
sentation? For the most part, commentators characterize the disagreement between
the Court majority and the dissent as a clash between a color-blind and a color-
conscious approach to the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
A central difficulty with the traditional interpretation, however, is that these recent
redistricting decisions do not adhere rigidly to a color-blind/color-conscious di-
chotomy; indeed, the Court majority floated unhappily between permitting the use
of “some” race as mandated by the Voting Rights Act, and forbidding the influence
of “too much” race on the basis that it presumptively violated the Constitution.
In contrast to the traditional interpretation, I develop an alternative theore-
tical approach to the recent redistricting cases, one that applies the insights of
Minority Representation, the Supreme Court, and the Politics of Democracy 35
democratic theory to the Supreme Court’s adjudication of minority represen-
tation.3In general, I argue that controversies over electoral redistricting are at
base disputes among competing visions of democracy. By crafting the rules and
standards that govern electoral redistricting, the Court implicitly adopted certain
theories of representation and embraced particular conceptions of democracy (see
also Issacharoff et al., 1998).4
A primary objective of this article is to identify and analyze the competing
visions of democracy in the Supreme Court’s new jurisprudence on minority
representation. While these (and other) conceptions of democracy animate
the Court’s voting rights jurisprudence as a whole, I focus specifically on the
rival conceptions of democracy in Shaw v. Reno (1993) and its progeny.5In
addition, I argue that these rival visions of democracy are often at the heart
of the apparent incoherence that marks the Court’s adjudication of minority
representation. Tensions among competing visions of democracy explain not
only the complexities of the majority opinion, but also help to explain the
deep divide between the majority and the dissent over the constitutionality of
majority-minority districts.6The Court’s understanding of democracy, it will be
shown, embodies a series of compromises among different visions of democracy,
leading to a jurisprudence that is often contradictory, evenincoherent, and at times
paradoxical.
Touncover these rival understandings of democracy, I treat the Supreme Court’s
decisions as political texts in their own right. I distinguish between the “explicit”
and the “implicit” visions of democracy in the Court’s recent redistricting cases.
By “explicit” visions of democracy, I am referring to what the Court itself
actually says about democracy and representation in its decisions. I analyze the
Court’s articulation of these conceptions of democracy, and show how these
understandings are relevant to the outcome of the cases. By “implicit” conceptions
of democracy, I am referring to those theories of democracy and representation
that are implied by the Court’sdecisions. That is, I examine how the Court’s consti-
tutional doctrines instantiate certain forms and understandings of democracy and
representation.
In Shaw v. Reno (1993) and its progeny, the majority and dissenting opinions
adopted fundamentally different visions of democracy.The Shaw majority adopted
an explicit vision of democracy that I refer to as “Individualist Democracy.” In the
majority’s vision, a system of government represents the interests of individuals,
and not groups, in the political process. When describing its conception of
democracy, the majority contended that race was not and should not be treated
as politically salient in the structure of a representative system. By contrast, the
dissenting opinion in Shaw v. Reno (1993) had an entirely different understanding
of democracy. The dissent’s explicit vision of democracy, which I refer to as

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT