Rule of law abolitionism

DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(07)00403-6
Pages53-89
Date18 January 2008
Published date18 January 2008
AuthorBenjamin S. Yost
RULE OF LAW ABOLITIONISM
Benjamin S. Yost
ABSTRACT
In the dark days of the 1980s and 1990s, the abolition of capital
punishment was virtually unthinkable. However, a new form of
abolitionism – which I call Rule of Law abolitionism – has raised the
hopes of death penalty opponents. In this chapter, I elucidate the logic of
the Rule of Law abolitionist argument, distinguishing it from its more
familiar doctrinal and moral variants. I then assess its strengths and
weaknesses. On the basis of this critique, I indicate the route Rule of Law
abolitionism must travel to bring about the demise of the death penalty.
The 1980s and 1990s were dark days for death penalty abolitionists. Rabid
public support for capital punishment combined with the Supreme Court’s
attacks on federal habeas corpus made abolition virtually unthinkable.
However, the emergence of a new form of abolitionism, coupled with the
growing power of the moratorium movement, has occasioned a remarkable
improvement in the abolitionist mood. I call this abolitionism ‘‘Rule of Law
abolitionism.’’
While certain versions of Rule of Law abolitionism, most notably the
‘‘new abolitionism’’ or ‘‘legally conservative abolitionism’’ championed by
Austin Sarat, have been discussed in the literature; there has been
insufficient analysis of its conceptual claims. This chapter will remedy this
oversight by illuminating the structure, logic, and specific content shared by
Special Issue: Is the Death Penalty Dying?
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society, Volume 42, 53–89
Copyright r2008 by Elsevier Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1016/S1059-4337(07)00403-6
53
different versions of Rule of Law abolitionism. Doing so will enable us to
understand better the strengths and weaknesses of Rule of Law abolition-
ism, which is crucial if we are to evaluate how, and to what degree, it might
contribute to the demise of capital punishment. This investigation is
especially important given the organizing premise of this volume: the
abolitionist movement is at a rare moment of opportunity, as the death
penalty has come under attack from unusual political, cultural, and religious
quarters.
Rule of Law abolitionism eschews controversial moral theory and futile
disagreement with the Supreme Court’s recent Eighth Amendment
jurisprudence. Instead, it stands on intuitive, non-polemical assertions
about the value of legal institutions. In the first part of the chapter, I
compare Rule of Law abolitionism to more familiar types of abolitionism:
(a) moral abolitionism, which argues that the death penalty violates
substantive moral values; and more importantly (b) doctrinal abolitionism,
which argues that the death penalty violates the U.S. Constitution. I then
detail the conceptual contours of Rule of Law abolitionism, with frequent
reference to the essays of Austin Sarat, Justice Harry Blackmun’s Callins
dissent, and seminal cases in the Supreme Court’s capital jurisprudence. (As
the reader will see, my conception of Rule of Law abolitionism is heavily
indebted to Austin Sarat’s ‘‘new abolitionism.’’) I show that Rule of Law
abolitionism begins with the intuition, honored in Furman and Gregg, that
legal violence must be more rational than extra-legal violence. Law’s
violence must be rational, rule-bound, and consistent. Rule of Law
abolitionists argue that capital sentencing cannot be rationalized, and
conclude that we must no longer ‘‘tinker with the machinery of death.’’
Indeed, Rule of Law abolitionism concludes, we have a duty to oppose
capital punishment. Along the way, I show that what distinguishes this
argument from doctrinal or moral ones is the claim that rationality is a
condition of legal legitimacy. Rule of Law abolitionists argue that by
continuing to execute, capital jurisdictions reduce law to a species of mere
coercion.
In the second part of the chapter, I submit Rule of Law abolitionism to
critical scrutiny. I first identify its important rhetorical advantages, showing
how Rule of Law abolitionism enables debates about capital punishment to
occur outside the moralistic vocabulary that so often hampers the
abolitionist cause. These benefits should not, however, obscure the
weaknesses of Rule of Law abolitionism. I argue that Rule of Law
abolitionism typically proves too much – its claim that sentencing
procedures cannot be rational and rule-bound bleeds into an unpalatable
BENJAMIN S. YOST54
argument against punishment as such. And some versions prove too little –
their procedural criticisms function as a roadmap for the reform, and
strengthening, of the capital punishment regime. Although these problems
complicate the promise of Rule of Law abolitionism, I conclude by
gesturing toward some conceptual modifications that will hopefully help
Rule of Law abolitionism realize its full potential.
THE DISTINCTIVENESS OF RULE OF LAW
ABOLITIONISM
Three types of abolitionist arguments have been made in the United States
in the past 50 years. I call them doctrinal abolitionism, Rule of Law
abolitionism, and moral abolitionism. Doctrinal abolitionists argue that
capital punishment is unconstitutional, and that the Supreme Court’s
capital jurisprudence since Gregg is wrong. Rule of Law abolitionists claim
that the death penalty violates Rule of Law values. Doctrinal abolitionism
and Rule of Law abolitionism are easily confused because they both invoke
the procedural values of rationality, consistency, and fairness. Both argue
that these values should trump other legal values (e.g., finality) whenever
there are conflicts in capital cases. The difference is that Rule of Law
abolitionism claims that Rule of Law values must prevail because they
legitimate legal violence, not because the Constitution says so. Rule of Law
abolitionism claims that Rule of Law values legitimate law, and therefore
cannot be given up in favor of other legal values. Rule of Law abolitionism’s
contrast with moral abolitionism is much sharper. Moral abolitionist
arguments proceed from premises found in moral philosophy and theology.
Moral abolitionists typically claim that capital punishment contravenes
substantive moral values such as human dignity.
To clarify the argument of Rule of Law abolitionism, I will first set it off
from doctrinal abolitionism. This discussion must begin with a caveat:
pure doctrinal abolitionists might not exist. I assume that most, if not all, of
the judges and lawyers who have a doctrinal disagreement with Gregg have
other reasons for opposing the death penalty.
1
This presents no problem
because I use terms such as ‘‘doctrinal abolitionism’’ (or ‘‘Rule of Law
abolitionism’’ or ‘‘moral abolitionism’’) to refer to certain types of
arguments, not to characterize people’s actual beliefs.
There are two types of doctrinal abolitionism. One contends that the
death penalty violates the Eighth Amendment’s cruel and unusual
Rule of Law Abolitionism 55

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT