The heart has its reasons: Examining the strange persistence of the American death penalty

Date18 January 2008
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(07)00402-4
Pages21-52
Published date18 January 2008
AuthorSusan A. Bandes
THE HEART HAS ITS REASONS:
EXAMINING THE STRANGE
PERSISTENCE OF THE AMERICAN
DEATH PENALTY
Susan A. Bandes
ABSTRACT
The debate about the future of the death penalty often focuses on whether
its supporters are animated by instrumental or expressive values, and if
the latter, what values the penalty does in fact express, where those values
originated and how deeply entrenched they are. In this chapter, I argue
that a more explicit recognition of the emotional sources of support for
and opposition to the death penalty will contribute to the clarity of the
debate. The focus on emotional variables reveals that the boundary
between instrumental and expressive values is porous; both types of values
are informed (or uninformed) by fear, outrage, compassion, selective
empathy and other emotional attitudes. More fundamentally, though
history, culture and politics are essential aspects of the discussion, the
resilience of the death penalty cannot be adequately understood when the
affect is stripped from explanations for its support. Ultimately, the death
penalty will not die without a societal change of heart.
Special Issue: Is the Death Penalty Dying?
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society, Volume 42, 21–52
Copyright r2008 by Elsevier Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1016/S1059-4337(07)00402-4
21
Before we can predict the fate of the death penalty, we need to understand
why capital punishment has persisted for so long in the United States. Why
have we continued to execute people into the twenty-first century, despite
evidence of wrongful executions, a lack of hard evidence of the penalty’s
efficacy and the increasing isolation of our position in the industrialized
world? The explanations for this persistence ought to provide insight
into the question of whether the death penalty is dying. Unfortunately, the
conventional discourse on this topic fails to adequately address one essential
aspect of the death penalty’s tenacity. As I will argue, the persistence of the
death penalty is incomprehensible without addressing the role of emotion.
The conventional discourse about capital punishment proceeds along
certain well-established, highly circumscribed paths. In general, it tracks
the usual philosophical debate about the purposes of punishment. The
traditional assumption is that capital punishment must serve an instru-
mental goal: deterrence, retribution or incapacitation. More recently, the
notion that capital punishment might serve goals that are expressive in
nature has gained currency. Questions about racial bias and systemic error
are counterpoised against these basic rationales, so that the question
becomes whether these problems with the system outweigh or detract from
the penalty’s penalogical goals. This is the shape of the legal and
philosophical debate about whether the death penalty is justified. It is also
the outward face of the public debate about the death penalty, since that
debate is often framed and summarized by social scientists and pollsters
whose questions track the traditional discourse (Ellsworth & Gross, 1994).
1
The rather salient emotional content of the question of whether or when
the state should kill is generally treated as a vexing and improper detour
from the rigors of proper legal analysis or the scope of legitimate debate.
This attitude toward emotion – a combination of denigration and denial –
shapes both the debate about whether capital punishment should be
maintained as a legitimate punishment and the debate about who should be
executed. It creates a two-track discussion, in which one track is regarded as
legally grounded, rigorous and acceptable and the other as illegitimate;
not part of the accepted legal language or structure. The result is deleterious
on two interrelated counts.
First, the ‘‘legally grounded’’ discussion, with its reference to time-
honored but affectless concepts like ‘‘deterrence’’ and ‘‘incapacitation,’’ fails
to describe with any accuracy the way people actually arrive at decisions
about the death penalty. The official ‘‘reasons’’ for the death penalty have
only a tenuous connection to the real reasons why people support capital
punishment. Researchers asking people why they support or oppose the
SUSAN A. BANDES22
death penalty repeatedly conclude that ‘‘most people’s attitudes toward
capital punishment are basically emotional. The ‘reasons’ are determined by
the attitude, not the reverse’’ (Ellsworth & Gross, 1994, p. 95).
Second, the official discourse, as currently structured, perpetuates a
misleading and problematic normative assumption: that the official reasons
are devoid of emotion (except, perhaps, for a few carefully managed,
‘‘allowable’’ emotions). Capital punishment discourse too often operates on
the assumption that rigorous, non-emotional reasons for or against the
death penalty exist, but that the conversation keeps getting hijacked by
unruly passion. I suggest that the reasons themselves, both the so-called
instrumental reasons and the so-called expressive reasons, are imbued with
emotional content. The boundary between instrumental and expressive
values is porous, and at bottom, both types of values are informed (or
uninformed) by fear, outrage, compassion, selective empathy and other
emotional attitudes. Or to put it another way, the decision whether or not to
maintain and implement our system of capital punishment is inherently an
expressive decision; one which is both inescapably moral and inescapably
emotional. The official discourse masks, sanitizes or denigrates much of this
emotional content. The result is not to banish emotion from the system, but
to drive discussion of it underground, to privilege certain emotions and to
perpetuate a system that depends on moral and emotional distance and even
disengagement.
The Court’s approach in California v. Brown (1986), in which it upheld a
jury instruction cautioning the jury that it ‘‘must not be swayed by mere
sentiment, conjecture, sympathy, passion, prejudice, public opinion or
public feeling’’ (p. 540), illustrates its misplaced faith in the existence of an
emotionless realm and how it privileges certain emotions. The Court was
confident that jurors would understand this instruction as a prohibition on
the exercise of ‘‘mere’’ or ‘‘untethered’’ sympathy, and would understand
that they were still permitted to exercise mercy or compassion. Justice
O’Connor, in her concurrence, explained that the instruction properly
recognized the jury’s decision as ‘‘a moral inquiry into the culpability of
the defendant, and not an emotional response to the mitigating evidence’’
(p. 545). Even apart from the question of how juries are to distinguish
sympathy, mere sympathy, mercy and compassion, the larger point is
that the Court mistakes the nature of moral decision making. Whether a
juror votes to take or spare a life will depend in large part on empathy,
distancing, anger, blame and other emotional variables, and these variables
will constitute an essential component of his moral decision (Haney, 1997;
Sundby, 2005). When the juror tries in good faith to fit these moral and
Examining the Strange Persistence of the American Death Penalty 23

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT