Ponzi, Property, and Luck

AuthorAndrew Kull
PositionDistinguished Senior Lecturer, University of Texas School of Law; Reporter, Restatement Third, Restitution and Unjust Enrichment
Pages291-322
291
Ponzi, Property, and Luck
Andrew Kull
“Ignorance is the best of law reformers. People are glad to discuss a question
on general principles, when they have forgotten the special knowledge
necessary for technical reasoning.”
1
I. INTRODUCTION ............................................................................. 291
II. SPECIAL KNOWLEDGE: FIVE PROPOSITIONS .................................. 294
III. MOVING THE PROPERTY BASELINE ................................................ 298
A. OWNERSHIP OF IDENTIFIABLE PROPERTY .................................. 298
B. OWNERSHIP OF AN IDENTIFIABLE PRODUCT. .............................. 302
C. OWNERSHIP OF FUNDS WITHDRAWN FROM THE SCHEME ............ 306
IV. GENERAL PRINCIPLES .................................................................... 312
A. INCENTIVES ............................................................................. 313
B. LOSS SHARING ........................................................................ 315
C. LUCK AND BLAME ................................................................... 318
V. CONCLUSION: A THOUGHT EXPERIMENT ..................................... 320
I. INTRODUCTION
Swindler is running a Ponzi scheme. Two or more victims invest with
Swindler in the hope of turning a profit. The scheme eventually collapses.
Some residue of the victims’ investments is found in the ruins, and the
question is how to divide it between the victims. The basis of the division is a
claim in restitution or unjust enrichment that is now asserted, explicitly or
otherwise, by one fraud victim against another. Remedies in such cases are
Distinguished Senior Lecturer, University of Texas School of Law; Reporter, Restatement
Third, Restitution and Unjust Enrichment. The encouragement of Ralph Brubaker, Ward Farnsworth,
Henry Smith, and Lionel Smith is gratefully acknowledged.
1. OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES, THE COMMON LAW 54 (1881).
292 IOWA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 100:291
predominantly equitable, and the question of allocation between victims is
sometimes described by comparing their “competing equities” or by asking
“what equity requires.” Courts have recently been giving new answers to this
old question. My topic is to ask why equity now seems to require something
different from what it required in the past.
The traditional answers came from the property-rights end of the equity
spectrum, the part that depends least on “equitable discretion.” But during
the second half of the 20th century, for a variety of reasons, the law of
equitable interests in property (as part of the law of restitution generally)
suffered a dramatic decline in professional attention and awareness—a story
that is old news by now.2 Propositions that were once part of what everyone
knew became doctrine that could only be found in the library, and then only
if one knew where to look. While this law was being forgotten, United States
courts were encountering an extraordinary upsurge in Ponzi-type cases.3 As it
happened, these cases fell to be litigated and decided by a new group of
American lawyers and judges: the first professional generation—roughly
speaking, of course—to attend law school after the courses dealing with
equitable interests in property had been dropped from the standard
curriculum.
Lack of awareness of the established rules has given courts an unusual
freedom to decide for themselves and afresh what equity requires between
victims of a common fraud. In three recurrent settings—all of them familiar
locations within the landscape where exploded Ponzi schemes fall to Earth—
recent decisions reach outcomes different from those that traditional
authority would dictate. Ignorance has not produced a random
redistribution, because the new results in victim v. victim cases have all been
pushed in the same direction. Courts spread losses more widely by refusing to
recognize the effects of fortuitous circumstances—luck—that by standard
property rules would occasionally permit a few relatively fortunate victims to
lose proportionately less than others. The move has been away from a view
that takes victims as it finds them, toward one that seeks to rationalize and to
equalize, so far as possible, the consequences of a casualty to which multiple
victims are thought to have been uniformly subject.
This shift in outcomes has redrawn the established map of property rights
by shortening the reach of legally protected ownership. By traditional rules,
2. See, e.g., Douglas Laycock, How Remedies Became a Field: A History, 27 REV. LITIG. 161, 173–74
(2008) (“As the [20th] century wore on, equity casebooks focused more on equitable remedies and
less on substantive equity.”). See generally John H. Langbein, The Later History of Restitution, in
RESTITUTION: PAST, PRESENT, AND FUTURE 57 (W.R. Cornish et al. eds., 1998); Andrew Kull,
Rationalizing Restitution, 83 CALIF. L. REV. 1191 (1995).
3. Anyone who reads the newspapers will share this impression, though I am not aware of
actual statistics. As a crude proxy, Westlaw reports that the name “Ponzi” appeared in 535 state
and federal decisions during the first 65 years of Charles Ponzi’s notoriety—or before January 1,
1985—and in approximately ten times as many since then. Decisions referring to “Ponzi” have
recently been added to the list at a rate of more than 600 per year.
2014] PONZI, PROPERTY, AND LUCK 293
the owner of an asset lost to fraud can retake it so long as it can be identified—
unless and until it comes into the hands of a bona fide purchaser. Protected
ownership thus extends beyond a misappropriation, ending only when
(1) the misappropriated asset can no longer be identified or (2) the rights of
a protected purchaser intervene. Because they deny the owner’s usual right
to restitution in such circumstances, recent decisions terminate ownership
earlier: at the point where the asset first leaves the owner’s hands.
Most of the recent victim v. victim decisions do not see the problem in
property terms. If they do, they assert—in the name of “equitable
discretion”—an overriding authority to reallocate whatever entitlements
might exist.4 More commonly, the courts—and the receivers whose rulings
the courts approve—see themselves as writing on a blank slate, subject to a
single guideline: a duty to divide contested property in whatever manner
seems best under the circumstances.5
My intention is not to criticize the courts for ignoring the rules.6 My
proposition is rather that the new outcomes in victim v. victim restitution cases
make a striking instance of Holmes’ law reform by ignorance. If we observe
that some “special knowledge” has evidently been forgotten, and that old
questions are being decided instead on “general principles”—and coming out
4. See, e.g., SEC v. Credit Bancorp, Ltd., 290 F.3d 80, 88 (2d Cir. 2002) (finding that the
existence of a constructive trust at state law “does not defeat the equitable authority of the District
Court to treat all the fraud victims alike (in proportion to their investments) and order a pro rata
distribution”); United States v. Vanguard Inv. Co., 6 F.3d 222, 226 (4th Cir. 1993) (finding
entitlement to restitution at state law, assuming it exists, may be disregarded by a court exercising
its “discretionary power” of equitable receivership). Invoked in this way, the asserted discretion
to reallocate state-law entitlements in the context of a federal receivership strongly resembles the
“free-wheeling equitable discretion to cut down entitlements when they are sought to be enforced
in a bankruptcy proceeding”—a discretion that does not exist:
Bankruptcy is an equitable procedure, and “equality is equity” (and vice versa), as
numerous bankruptcy cases intone. These truisms have a particular appeal for those
bankruptcy judges who would like to administer the bankruptcy laws in accordance
with their personal notions of fairness. But it is now well settled that although the
origins, procedures, and many of the remedies of bankruptcy a re indeed equitable,
a bankruptcy judge has no authority to cut down the entitlements that creditors seek
to enforce in bankruptcy, except as provided by the Bankruptcy Code itself.
In re Stoecker, 179 F.3d 546, 551 (7th Cir. 1999) (Posner, C.J.) (citations omitted). If the idea
of the present discussion were to criticize the recent Ponzi cases on the ground that they were
incorrectly decided, a good way to start would be to demonstrate that a federal equity receiver
has no more power to cut down state-law property entitlements than does a bankr uptcy judge.
My present purpose is different, as I am about to explain.
5. “There are no hard rules governing a district court’s decisions in matters like these. The
standard is whether a distribution is equitable and fair in the eyes of a reasonable judge.” SE C v.
Enter. Trust Co., No. 08 C 1260, 2008 WL 4534154, at *3 (N.D. Ill. Oct. 7, 2008).
6. For criticism along these mor e traditional lines see, for example, RESTATEMENT (THIRD)
OF RESTITUTION & UNJUST ENRICHMENT § 59 & cmt. g and accompanying Reporter’s Note
(2011); Chaim Saiman, Restitution and the Production of Legal Doctrine, 65 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 993,
998 (2008).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT