Nudging and the choice architecture of offending decisions

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/1745-9133.12470
AuthorGreg Pogarsky,Shaina Herman
Date01 November 2019
Published date01 November 2019
DOI: 10.1111/1745-9133.12470
RESEARCH ARTICLE
NUDGING & CHOICE IN OFFENDING DECISIONS
Nudging and the choice architecture of offending
decisions
Greg Pogarsky Shaina Herman
University at Albany,State University of New
York
Correspondence
GregPogarsky, School of Criminal Justice,
Universityat Albany, State Universityof New
York,135 WesternAvenue, Draper Hall 219,
Albany,NY 12222.
Email:gpogarsky@albany.edu
Research Summary: Deterring crime is often considered
to be a process of information transmission (e.g., Geerken
& Gove, 1975). Economic notions on incentives and
choice have meshed well with this perspective (Becker,
1968; Matsueda, 2013). Behavioral economics, however,
represents a source of further insights on offender decision-
making, particularly regarding information transmission to
promote conformity. Pogarsky, Roche, and Pickett (2018)
reviewed behavioraleconomic studies of offender decision-
making in criminology. In their review, they focused on
prospect theory (Kahneman & Tversky,1979), a behavioral
economic model of decision-making. More recently, Kah-
neman (2003, 2011) highlighted the dual-process nature
of behavioral economics, and Thaler and Sunstein (2009)
elaborated some principles of nudging. These notions
underscore dimensions of offending decisions beyond the
perceived costs, risks, and benefits of crime.
Policy Implications: From a behavioral economic stand-
point, there is a choice architecture to offending decisions
that permits various prosocial nudges. We analyze these
ideas for possible theoretical innovations and alternative
perspectives on crime policy.
KEYWORDS
behavioral economics, decision-making, deterrence, dual process, nudge
Beginning in the late 1950s, rates of drug, property, and violent crime increased precipitously until
the great crime drop of the early 1990s. These increases coincided with the permissive social and legal
climate of the 1960s and the U.S. Supreme Court’s expansionof cr iminal defendants’r ights under Chief
Criminology & Public Policy. 2019;18:823–839. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/capp © 2019 American Society of Criminology 823
824 POGARSKY AND HERMAN
Justice Earl Warren.1During this time, Becker (1968) initiated a period of sustained economic thinking
about crime research and policy. The view took hold that crime increased because it became steadily
less risky and costly for potential offenders. The policy response entailed increasingly punitive crime
control beginning in the 1990s, a period often termed mass incarceration. The linkage to economics
was clear. Becker (1995, p. 6) declared “prison works and, barring any more effective methods, is
useful.” To disincentivize and reduce crime, Becker (1995, p. 9) advocated for “law-and-order-type
policies” like sentence enhancements, stop-and-frisk, more prisons, and three-strike policies.
Ensuing policy initiatives mostly aligned with these recommendations, but now there is widespread
consensus for a less monolithic approach that better comports with recent research findings on crim-
inal deterrence and human decision-making. Criminology lacks consensus on the empirical status of
deterrence principles (e.g., Chalfin & McCrary, 2017; Loughran, Paternoster, Chalfin, & Wilson, 2016;
Pratt, Cullen, Blevins, Daigle, & Madensen, 2006; Tonry, 2008). There is also conflicting evidenceon
key contingencies for deterrence. For example, some researchers have found that criminal propensity
diminishes (e.g., Nagin & Paternoster, 1993; Piquero & Tibbetts 1996), whereas others have found
that propensity enhances (Pogarsky, 2007; Tittle, Ward, & Grasmick, 2004; Wright, Caspi, Moffitt, &
Paternoster, 2004), legal deterrent effects.
Thus, receptiveness to new perspectives has grown. In one such perspective,behavioral economics,
the signature “rational actor” assumption of economic theory is relaxed (Dhami, 2016; Kahneman,
2011; Thaler & Gasner, 2015). Pogarsky, Roche, and Pickett (2018) outlined recent advancements on
offender decision-making that are attributable to behavioral economics. They devoted considerable
attention in their review to prospect theory (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979), a “quasi-rational” model of
decision processes generally considered part of system 2.2More recently,researchers have expounded
the dual-systems aspects of behavioral economics. Kahneman and Frederick (2002, p. 51) observed
that, “[C]ognitive processes can be partitioned into two main families – traditionally called intuition
and reason.” Kahneman (2011) explained that system 2 processes are controlled, effortful, slow, self-
aware, rule-following, and effable. In contrast, system 1 processes are intuitive, automatic, effortless,
fast, unconscious, and ineffable (Thaler & Sunstein, 2009). According to Kahneman (2003), system 1
instinctual processes run continuously, whereas system 2 stays in “low effort mode.” System 2 often
remains unengaged; involvement takes effort and is thus reserved for times when system 1 encounters
difficulty or dissonance.
Although much prior research on offender decision-making has targeted system 2 processes, dual-
process thinking is becoming increasingly evident in criminology.A prominent example is the hot/cool
perspective of van Gelder and de Vries (2012, 2014). The hot mode of processing is affective and
based on emotions such as fear and anger. The cool mode entails the type of dispassionate reason-
ing associated with rational choice theories of crime. Behavioral economics has a broader conception
of system 1 than this; it includes visceral influences but also intuitions and cognitive heuristics or
shortcuts. Thomas and McGloin (2013) invoked dual-process reasoning to distinguish normative peer
influences, which involve attitudinal change over time, from socializing peer influences that are more
momentary. Mamayek, Loughran, and Paternoster (2015) applied dual-process principles to distin-
guish core decision-making constructs, such as impulsivity, self-control, and thoughtfully reflective
decision-making (TRDM; Paternoster, Pogarsky, & Zimmerman, 2011). Our aim in this article is to
examine the dual-process aspects of behavioral economics for potential innovations in crime theory
and policy.
As Thaler, Sunstein, and Balz (2010, p. 428) explained, “People do not make choices in a vacuum.
They make them in an environment where many features, noticed and unnoticed, can influence their
decisions.” This environment comprises a choice architecture for offending decisions. In turn, vari-
ous nudges are possible that leverage aspects of the choice architecture toward conformity. Thaler and

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT