Moral Justifications on the Rehnquist Court

AuthorJames A. Woods,Bradley Stewart Chilton
DOI10.1177/0887403405284859
Published date01 September 2006
Date01 September 2006
Subject MatterArticles
10.1177/0887403405284859Criminal Justice Policy ReviewChilton, Woods / Moral Justifications on Rehnquist Court
Moral Justifications on
the Rehnquist Court
Hercules, Herbert, and “Druggies” Under
the Fourth Amendment
Bradley Stewart Chilton
Appalachian State University
James A. Woods
Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts
What moral justifications do we find in Fourth Amendment judicial opinions of the
Rehnquist Court, and what does this suggest about future Court decision making? First,
the authors develop the moral justification model of judicial decision making in a litera-
ture review,with linguistic patterns and categories by Hercules and Herbert for content
analysis. Second, they discuss the methodological strategies used in this content analysis
of official opinions of the Court on the Fourth Amendment from 1986 to 1994. Third,
from this content analysis, the authors describe the patterns of moral justification in
Rehnquist Court Fourth Amendment opinions, including the Court’s assessments of the
moral virtue of “druggie” defendants. Finally, they draw conclusions from this analysis
for a moral science of the politics of law.
Keywords: Rehnquist Court; FourthAmendment; moral justifications
There has been a rebirth of moral inquiry in the social sciences, overcoming old
fears of conformity, intolerance, and idiosyncratic and superstitious approaches
to morality. Social scientists such as James Q. Wilson, Amartya Sen, Robert Bellah,
Carol Gilligan, and many others have persuaded social scientists to attend to the moral
aspects of social phenomena. Morality is not relegated to the heap of traditionalism
343
Criminal Justice
Policy Review
Volume 17 Number 3
September 2006 343-361
© 2006 Sage Publications
10.1177/0887403405284859
http://cjp.sagepub.com
hosted at
http://online.sagepub.com
Authors’Note: The opinions expressed in this article are those of the authors and are not to be viewed as a
statement of the official viewsof the Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts. We gratefully acknowledge
the efforts of the many students of Professor Chilton’s graduateseminar at the University of North Texas
(CJUS 5870–Criminal Evidence) in assistance in data collection, content analysis, analysis, and discussion
ofthis project. We also acknowledge a former student, TracyGoss Wolf, who applied this justification theory
to the Burger Court’s FourthAmendment decision making in her M.A. thesis on which we served as chair
(Chilton) and reader (Woods)at the University of Toledo and in a article Professor Chilton coauthored with
Ms. Wolf for the 1996 Academy of Criminal Justice Sciences meeting, “Towarda Justification Theory of
JudicialDecisions: Chief Justice WarrenEarl Burger and the Fourth Amendment.” This article continues the
developmentof a moral justification theory first espoused by Chilton as a graduate student in a 1983 article
and conformity, for even the liberal belief in individual freedoms is itself a moral
belief about state evenhandedness among the competing conceptions of the good life.
Fears of an imperialistic and intolerant morality are unfounded; in reality, moral
inquiry most threatens the identity politics of those who believe that pluralism should
not involvea genuine give-and-take with others. And the dismissal of morality as idio-
syncratic, superstitious, and merely the “will to power” would similarly make all
social science impossible and anarchistic; objectivity is as possible and desirable in a
moral science as in any other (Wolfe, 1999).
The revivalof moral inquiry in the social sciences has prospered particularly in the
study of the politics of law (Murphy,Pritchett, & Epstein, 2002, p. 17). After decades
of skepticism in legal realism, legal positivism, and economic and critical legal stud-
ies, a growing group of scholars and practitioners have argued against moral relativ-
ism and legal positivism and posited alternatives,including “moral realism” (Barber,
1993; Moore, 1985, 1992) and “deep conventionalism” (e.g., Dworkin, 1978, 1986,
1996). Not limited to merely some revival of “natural law” jurisprudence, these
diverse scholars havesought to more systematically understand amoral science of law
(e.g., Ackerman, 1991; Bobbitt, 1982; Bork, 1990; Chilton, 1998; Levinson, 1988;
Perry, 1982; Powell,1993; Smith, 1985; Sunstein, 1990; Tushnet, 1988) and applica-
tions, such as public administration (e.g., T. Cooper, 1991; Green, 1992; Rohr,1978;
Rosenbloom & O’Leary, 1997).
Although these explorations into the moral science of law greatly illuminate the
ethical reality of legal phenomena, they frequently proceed without a rich appreciation
of specific cases and an empirical, hardnosed inquiry. Moral studies by practitioners
give valuable attention to the special problems of moral reasoning that stem from
actual experiences as participants (e.g., Bork, 1990; Zitrin & Langford, 1999) but
leave much to be desired when compared against a systematic understanding of the
moral science of law. Case studies and biographies of individual justices typically
assess the compliance of an individualdecision or judge with a moral principle or ethic
(e.g., Dworkin, 1985; Gerber, 2002), but these external, post hoc studies of moral
compliance do not offer a systematic understanding of a moral science of law.
It is fitting at this time that we systematically examine the moral underpinnings of
the Rehnquist Court’s opinions with the end of the Rehnquist Court and the beginning
of the Roberts Court. To be sure, there are rich descriptions, biographies, and some
analyses of the moral science of law, especially of the Rehnquist Court. There are
excellent biographies and analyses of the moral underpinnings of legal interpretation
of justices on the Rehnquist Court (e.g., Yarbrough, 2001). There are applications of
ethics and philosophy of law to illuminate how Rehnquist Court justices base deci-
sions on their philosophies and ethics. And a number of political analyses touch on
issues of the moral underpinnings of the Court’s decisions (e.g., P. Cooper, 1999;
Garbus, 2002; Schwartz, 2003; Simon, 1999). These analyses and many others have
344 Criminal Justice Policy Review
presented at the American Political Science Association meeting, “Rights and the Politics of Faith.” It is
wonderful to learn from and with our students,as well as the many scholars with whom we discussed these
ideas, but we take full blame for any shortcomings.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT