Financial Markets Where Traders Neglect the Informational Content of Prices

AuthorMATTHEW RABIN,DIMITRI VAYANOS,ERIK EYSTER
Date01 February 2019
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jofi.12729
Published date01 February 2019
THE JOURNAL OF FINANCE VOL. LXXIV, NO. 1 FEBRUARY 2019
Financial Markets Where Traders Neglect the
Informational Content of Prices
ERIK EYSTER, MATTHEW RABIN, and DIMITRI VAYANOS
ABSTRACT
We model a financial market where some traders of a risky asset do not fully appreci-
ate what prices convey about others’ private information. Markets comprising solely
such “cursed” traders generate more trade than those comprising solely rationals. Be-
cause rationals arbitrage away distortions caused by cursed traders, mixed markets
can generate even more trade. Per-trader volume in cursed markets increases with
market size; volume may instead disappear when traders infer others’ information
from prices, even when they dismiss it as noisier than their own. Making private in-
formation public raises rational and “dismissive” volume, but reduces cursed volume
given moderate noninformational trading motives.
EVER SINCE MILGROM AND STOKEY (1982) and Tirole (1982), researchers have
understood that common knowledge of rationality combined with a common
prior precludes purely speculative trade. Of course, people might rationally
trade financial assets for a variety of nonspeculative motives, such as portfolio
rebalancing and liquidity. Yet even in settings where the presence of nonspec-
ulative motives allows for speculative trade, a rational understanding of the
adverse selection problem causes the overall volume of trade to be constrained
by nonspeculative motives. In many people’s estimation, trading volume in fi-
nancial markets greatly exceeds what can be plausibly explained by models
applying rational expectations equilibrium (REE).1
Erik Eyster is at the London School of Economics. Matthew Rabin is at Harvard University.
Dimitri Vayanos is at the London School of Economics, CEPR, and NBER. We thank Nick Bar-
beris; Bruno Biais (the Editor); John Campbell; Kent Daniel; Willie Fuchs; Xavier Gabaix; Tristan
Gagnon-Bartsch; Josh Schwartzstein; Andrei Shleifer; Jeremy Stein; Xavier Vives; Liyan Yang;
an anonymous Associate Editor and two referees; seminar participants at Cambridge, Columbia,
Copenhagen, Harvard/MIT, Humboldt, NYU Stern, Oxford, UC Berkeley, UC Davis, and Whar-
ton; and participants at the Barcelona Graduate School in Economics Summer Forum, Miami
Behavioral Finance Conference, NBER Behavioral Finance Conference, Paris School of Economics
Workshop in Bounded Rationality, Toulouse School of Economics Conference in honor of Jean Ti-
role, SAET (Rio), and Stanford Institute for Theoretical Economics for helpful comments. We also
thank Tristan Gagnon-Bartsch, TarsoMori Madeira, and Gianluca Rinaldi for research assistance.
Financial support from the Paul Woolley Centre at the London School of Economics is gratefully
acknowledged. We have read the Journal of Finance disclosure policy and have no conflicts of
interest to disclose.
1For example, in his presidential address to the American Finance Association, French (2008)
notes that, while the capitalized cost of trading exceeds 10% of market capitalization, turnover in
DOI: 10.1111/jofi.12729
371
372 The Journal of Finance R
Researchers have sought to explain excessive trading volume by relaxing the
common-prior assumption. Harrison and Kreps (1978) show that noncommon
priors about an asset’s payoff generate volume in a dynamic model where risk-
neutral traders cannot sell the asset short. Scheinkman and Xiong (2003)use
Harrison and Kreps’s framework to examine traders who are “overconfident.” In
their setting, all traders observe all signals about the payoff, but certain traders
overestimate the information content of certain signals.2In these models with-
out private information, trade derives from traders agreeing to disagree about
the relationship between payoff and public information—the lack of private
information disencumbers traders from the need to invert market prices.3A
second approach incorporates noncommon priors into incomplete-information
models by assuming that privately informed traders agree to disagree
about the precision of traders’ private information. Daniel, Hirshleifer, and
Subrahmanyam (1998) and Odean (1998), for example, show that traders’ over-
confidence about the precision of their private information can increase trad-
ing volume. Similarly, Odean (1998), Banerjee, Kaniel, and Kremer (2009),
Banerjee and Kremer (2010), and Banerjee (2011) show that when traders
downplay the precision of one another’s private signals—which we call
dismissiveness—volume increases.4In this second class of agreeing-to-disagree
models, the presence of private information infuses market prices with infor-
mation content, and traders are assumed to fully invert market prices to un-
cover others’ information. Both types of agreeing-to-disagree models consider
traders who recognize their disagreements in beliefs—and trade because of
these recognized disagreements.
In this paper, we propose a different conceptual approach to explaining spec-
ulative trade: people trade because they neglect disagreements in beliefs. We
capture this idea in a simple and tractable model where some or all traders,
when choosing their demands, do not fully invert prices to uncover others’ in-
formation. This approach builds on extensive evidence, reviewed in Section IV,
that people do not sufficiently heed the information content of others’ behavior,
even in the absence of intrinsic disagreements.
2007 was 215%, which creates a puzzle: “from the perspective of the negative-sum game, it is hard
to understand why equity investors pay to turn their aggregate portfolio over more than two times
in 2007” (p. 1552).
2Hong, Scheinkman, and Xiong (2006) model overconfidence similarly,also allowing for hetero-
geneous priors, in a model where the number of shares of a risky asset increases over time.
3Other models of trade deriving from differences in beliefs include Lintner (1969)andVarian
(1985), in which traders have different subjective priors; De Long et al. (1990), in which symmet-
rically informed traders disagree because some of them (“noise traders”) misperceive next-period
prices for exogenous reasons; Harris and Raviv (1993) and Kandel and Pearson (1995), in which
traders disagree about the informativeness of public signals; and Biais and Bossaerts (1998), in
which traders are uncertain about others’ belief hierarchy. Hong and Stein (2007) summarize this
literature. Eyster and Piccione (2013) model traders with incomplete theories of price formation,
also in a complete-information setting.
4Banerjee, Kaniel, and Kremer (2009), Banerjee and Kremer (2010), and Banerjee (2011)use
the term “differences of opinion” to describe the heterogeneity in beliefs that drives their mod-
els. We instead use the term dismissiveness, to distinguish it from overconfidence or from other
disagreements about signal structures that can create differences of opinion.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT