Contracts with Wishful Thinkers

AuthorMaria Grazia Romano,Giovanni Immordino,Anna Maria C. Menichini
Published date01 October 2015
Date01 October 2015
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jems.12113
Contracts with Wishful Thinkers
GIOVANNI IMMORDINO
Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche e Statistiche
University of Naples Federico II, Via Cintia Monte S. Angelo, 80122, Napoli, Italy,and CSEF
giovanni.immordino@unina.it
ANNA MARIA C. MENICHINI
Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche e Statistiche
University of Salerno, Via Giovanni Paolo II, 84084 Fisciano (SA), Italy,and CSEF
amenichini@unisa.it
MARIA GRAZIA ROMANO
Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche e Statistiche
University of Salerno, Via Giovanni Paolo II, 84084 Fisciano (SA), Italy,and CSEF
maromano@unisa.it
In a setting with a wishful thinking agent and a realistic principal, the paper studies how incentive
contracts should be designed to control for both moral hazard and self-deception. The properties
of the contract that reconcile the agent with reality depend on the weight the agent attaches
to anticipatory utility. When this is small, principal and agent agree on full recollection. For
intermediate values the principal bears an extra cost to make the agent recall bad news. For large
weights, the principal gives up on inducing signal recollection. We also extend the analysis to
the case in which the parameter of anticipatory utility is private information.
1. Introduction
There is widespread psychological evidence that most individuals hold overly positive
evaluations about the self and exaggerated perceptions of control or unrealistic opti-
mism (Taylor and Brown, 1988).1Recent economic literature has tried to reconcile this
with individual decision making, by constructing models with endogenously wishful
thinkers. The present paper introduces moral hazard in such a model and studies an
employment contract between an endogenously optimistic agent and a realistic princi-
pal. Optimism is modeled assuming that the agent enjoys anticipatory utility, that is,
derives utility from the anticipation of his future payoff: the greater his futurepayoff, the
greater his current utility. A greater anticipatory utility can be achieved by suppressing
current bad information affecting future payoffs, thus expecting good outcomes more
We thank the editor, Daniel Spulber, an associate editor, and two anonymous referees for comments and
suggestions that greatly improved the paper. We are also indebted to Utpal Bhattacharya, Yeon-Koo Che,
Andy Newman, and Marco Pagano for many useful insights, and participants to the the First Workshop
ME@Velia(Ascea Marina), to the 6th CSEF-IGIER Symposium in Economics and Institutions (Capri), as well
as seminar participants at the Universit´
e de Paris Dauphine (Paris) and Cass Business School (London) for
their comments. A previous version has been circulated under the title “Optimal compensation contracts for
optimistic managers.” Usual disclaimer applies.
1. In the economic literature, such attitudes are especially documented for businessmen. For example,
Cooper et al. (1988) argue that entrepreneurs see their own chances for success higher than that of their peers,
whereas Malmendier and Tate(2005) and Malmendier and Tate (2008) find evidence that CEOs overestimate
their firms’ future performance.
C2015 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.
Journal of Economics & Management Strategy, Volume24, Number 4, Winter 2015, 863–886
864 Journal of Economics & Management Strategy
often than is warranted. But because distorted beliefs distort actions, optimism has an
influence on decisions and exacerbates incentive problems. We study how the need to
control for both optimism and moral hazard affects the design of incentive contracts.
To analyze this problem, we develop a model that unifies various themes from
psychology and economics within a simple contract-theoretic framework. According to
an influential literature in psychology (Taylor and Brown, 1988), normal mental func-
tioning is skewed in a positive direction and processes of self deception—the active
misrepresentation of reality to the conscious mind—are characteristic of mental health
(Trivers,2000). The resulting biases guide the processing of information, such that mildly
negative or ambiguous information is distorted to be more positive than may actually be
the case. In particular, individuals adjust to threatening events by constructing benign
interpretations of the same events.2One of the many forces that may favor mechanisms
of self-deception is that positive illusions may give intrinsic benefits (Taylor and Brown,
1988; Trivers, 2000). As Taylor (1989) describes it, “It is just as easy to construe future
events in a manner that promises success and happiness rather than one that portends
failure. Self-deception can be healthful and bolstering if it doesn’t involve gambling one’s
resources beyond salvage.” The beneficial effect of self-deception is modeled in the eco-
nomic literature by assuming that prior to the resolution of uncertainty, individuals
experience feelings of anticipation. Through imperfect memory, they select their beliefs
so as to enjoy the greatest comfort or happiness, thus leading to cognitive dissonance.
However, thereare limits to the extent of self-deception. “At one level, [the normal
human mind] constructs beneficent interpretations of threatening events that raise self-
esteem and promote motivation; yet at another level, it recognizes the threat or challenge
that is posed by these events” (Taylor, 1989). Tocapture the “consciousness/awareness”
that rejoins individuals with reality, most of the theoretical literature has assumed indi-
viduals to be Bayesian information processors (Piccione and Rubinstein, 1997; B´
enabou
and Tirole, 2002): they areaware of the flaws of memory and in making choices take into
account the possibility of having suppressed unfavorable information.3
Our paper builds on this literature and by applying a game of belief management
`
alaB
´
enabou and Tirole (2002) into a principal-agent framework with wishful thinking
agents, inquires into how a principal should reward a forgetful agent in the aware-
ness that well-designed payoffs can limit his tendency to self-deception. The agent’s
forgetfulness is modeled as in B´
enabou (2008) and B´
enabou (2013), which incorporates
anticipatory utility into the model of B´
enabou and Tirole (2002). The contracting frame-
work we adopt represents a further mechanism through which the individual can be
reconciled with reality and is the main contribution of this paper.
In our model, a risk-neutral principal hires a risk-neutral agent for a project. When
the principal offers the contract, the parties are symmetrically informed. If the agent
accepts, he chooses a level of effort that affects the project’s probability of success. After
signing but before choosing his unobservable effort, the agent receives a private signal
about the profitability of the task. A good signal implies a high return in case of success
and a bad signal only an intermediate return. Finally, in case of failure, the return is zero
regardless of type of signal. If the signal is informative about the return from effort, the
agent would benefit from having accurate news. However, because he derives utility
2. Freud (1940, 1957) argues that when events fromthe internal and external world are highly threatening,
people may deny or represstheir implications in order to avoid intolerable anxiety. Denial involves a distortion
of negative experiences so complete that it can block out the memory of the experience altogether (cited in
Taylor, 1989).
3. See Mullainathan (2002) for the case of naive decision makers.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT