When is strict criminal liability just?
Author | Simons, Kenneth W. |
-
Introduction
The most vigorous condemnation of strict liability in criminal law
comes from retributivists, not from utilitarians. Strict liability appears
to be a straightforward case of punishing the blameless, an approach
that might have consequential benefits but is unfair on any
retrospective theory of just deserts.(1) More precisely, strict liability is
condemned by culpability-based rather than harm-based retributivists.(2) If
retributive desert depends only on harm caused, then strict criminal
liability is hardly problematic. But if desert instead depends on
culpability in bringing about a harm or wrong, then strict criminal liability
seems flatly inconsistent with retributive theory.
It might seem obvious that strict liability is inconsistent with
culpability-based retributivism. But what, exactly, do such retributivists
condemn? Is their condemnation always justified? I will suggest that
it is not.
To give an adequate answer to these last questions, we need to
examine more carefully a number of issues: different categories of
strict liability; the way in which criminal offenses are structured; the
scope of the moral luck principle; negligence in grading; and the
distinction between rules and standards. I will conclude, perhaps
unsurprisingly, that strict liability is a genuine problem for retributive
theory. But I also reach a more interesting conclusion: Strict liability
is a different and more subtle problem, and in certain ways both a less
serious and a more serious problem, than it is generally believed to
be.
Let me begin with two examples to set the stage. First, suppose
that a rash of forest fires prompts a legislature to consider enacting a
law prohibiting any person from causing a forest fire, with a penalty of
five years imprisonment. The powerful lobby of culpability-based
retributivist law professors raises a public alarm about this "strict
liability" proposal. So the legislature responds by enacting a law
prohibiting any person from knowingly carrying a match in or near a
forest, with a penalty of five years imprisonment if any person who
knowingly carries a match thereby causes a forest fire. Should the law
professors be appeased? We will see that they should not be, since the
modified proposal expresses a formal rather than substantive kind of
fault. In substance, that is, the proposal imposes strict liability, by
failing to require a degree or type of culpability sufficient to justify
punishment on a retributive theory. Should the law professors be
appeased if the government instead passes a law setting a smaller
penalty simply for knowingly carrying a match in or near a forest? This, I
will argue, raises similar concerns, though it might be consistent with
retributive blame.
Second, consider the crime of felony-murder. Notwithstanding
the vigorous criticism of retributivists (among others), many
American state legislatures continue to treat very harshly defendants who
commit felonies that cause a death, even if the defendant displays
little or no culpability as to the death itself.(3) Utilitarian and harm-based
retributivist justifications have been offered for felony-murder
statutes. But this article will suggest that culpability-based retributivism
can partially justify such statutes, as partially expressing both a more
substantive conception of fault, and a familiar principle of moral luck.
It will also conclude, however, that retributivism cannot fully justify
the severity of many felony-murder statutes.
The scope of the article is broad, but not unlimited. The article
does not separately examine the voluntary act requirement,(4) nor the
minimum culpability that retributive theory requires. In a previous
essay, I have argued that a form of culpable indifference is the
necessary minimum,(5) but the arguments in this article would remain
essentially the same if one reached a different conclusion about the
requisite minimum -- e.g., if one concluded that tort negligence, gross
negligence, or some form of recklessness is the required minimum
culpability. For simplicity, the article refers throughout to
"negligence" as a minimally acceptable form of fault.
Moreover, the article presents these arguments as ideal
justifications, i.e., as constraints that a legislature would accept if it
chose to rely on culpability-based retribution as its exclusive theory of
punishment. In fact, of course, arguments of harm-based retribution and
deterrence often play a major role in shaping criminal legislation.
Although culpability-based retributivism does find some doctrinal
expression in the state and federal constitutional limits on criminal
legislation,(6) and in some judicial interpretive practices,(7) that doctrinal
expression will not be my focus.
Most crucially, perhaps, the article says little about which
particular version of retributive theory is most attractive (or most consistent
with legal doctrine). As a consequence, some important questions will
not be fully resolved. My apparent diffidence is for a reason: to
enable the arguments in this article to have force for a variety of
retributive views. For example, the article accepts the possibility that
retributive theory countenances moral luck (i.e., that an actor
deserves greater moral blame if his culpable conduct fortuitously results
in harm than if it does not).
Section II sets forth some preliminary distinctions, including the
distinction between pure and impure strict liability, and between strict
liability in criminalizing and strict liability in grading. Section III
demonstrates that conventional analysis expresses a formal
conception of strict liability (and fault), a conception that is both too weak
and too strong relative to a substantive conception of strict liability
(and fault). Section IV examines more closely how mens rea and
actus reus, separately and in combination, express culpability under a
substantive retributive theory. I examine in some detail and partially
criticize the view that retributive theory supports a sharp distinction
between wrongdoing (the ultimate harm) and culpability (in the
sense of the actor's mental state). Section V, addressing moral luck,
suggests that strict liability is unacceptable when it amounts to a broad
principle of substitute culpability, but might be acceptable when it
simply expresses the principle of moral luck.
The next part, Section VI, examines cases in which formal strict
liability in grading actually expresses culpability (especially
negligence). Subsections A and B set forth two very different ways in which
this can be true -- when formal strict liability in grading represents
substantive negligence, and when strict liability is a rule-like form of
negligence. A third subsection examines a less persuasive
argument -- that strict liability can be defended as a form of genuine fault in
the sense of a requirement of "extraordinary care."
Section VII responds to a natural objection to. the thesis. Why not
permit a defense of non-negligence in an cases, even if it would be
gratuitous in many? The answer builds on earlier analysis: Such a
defense would undermine retributive desert when strict liability
expresses no more than the moral luck principle, when strict liability is a
(justifiable) rule-like form of negligence, and when the comparable
culpability principle applies.
-
Some Preliminaries
Before exploring the substantive arguments about the proper
scope of strict criminal liability, it is important to clarify some relevant
concepts. We need to differentiate strict liability with respect to
results, circumstances, and conduct; to distinguish pure from impure
strict liability; and to distinguish strict liability in criminalizing from
strict liability in grading.
Strict criminal liability is conventionally understood as criminal
liability that does not require the defendant to possess a culpable state
of mind.(8) Modern criminal codes typically include as possible
culpable states of mind the defendant's intention to bring about a
prohibited result, her belief that such a result will follow or that a
prohibited circumstance will exist, her recklessness as to such a result or
circumstance, or her negligence with respect to such a result or
circumstance.(9) Strict criminal liability, then, is simply liability in the
absence of intention, belief, recklessness, or negligence.
We must also distinguish between strict liability with respect to a
result element of an offense and strict liability with respect to a
circumstance element.(10) Felony-murder, in its most severe form, is an
example of strict liability with respect to a result -- specifically, a death
resulting from commission of the felony. That is, the felon will be
liable for the resulting death as if he had intended it, even if there is
no proof of intent, or (perhaps) of any culpability, as to that result.
Statutory rape is a common example of strict liability with respect
to a circumstance -- specifically, the circumstance of whether the
female victim is below the statutory age. A defendant can be guilty of
statutory rape even if there is no proof that he believed, or reasonably
should have believed, that she was below the statutory age. Thus,
strict liability encompasses both liability for faultless accidents (in
bringing about a prohibited result) and for faultless mistakes (in
assessing whether a prohibited circumstance exists).(11)
Strict liability can also refer, not to lack of culpability with respect
to a result or a circumstance, but to lack of culpable conduct. That is,
the actus reus of the crime might specify and prohibit certain conduct
(whether action or omission) by the defendant. For example, a
prohibition on driving an automobile above the statutory speed limit can
be understood as imposing strict liability, insofar as it is irrelevant that
the defendant did not have reason to know that she was traveling at
that speed.(12) (Although there is something to be said for assimilating
the...
To continue reading
Request your trialCOPYRIGHT GALE, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.