Unpacking Negligence Liability: Experimentally Testing the Governance Effect

AuthorTheodore Eisenberg,Christoph Engel
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jels.12099
Published date01 March 2016
Date01 March 2016
Unpacking Negligence Liability:
Experimentally Testing the
Governance Effect
Theodore Eisenberg and Christoph Engel*
Arguably, if a court holds a defendant liable for negligently inflicting harm on the plaintiff,
this intervention combines three effects: (1) the court specifies the normative expectation,
(2) the court expresses dissatisfaction with the plaintiff’s behavior, for example, her level of
activity, and (3) the court obliges the defendant to compensate the plaintiff. In the field, it
would be close to impossible to disentangle the three effects, or to investigate how they
interact with intrinsic reticence to inflict harm on a passive outsider. We therefore go to the
lab. We do not find an effect of intrinsic morality. However, the intervention has a separate
significant effect on each of the three channels.
I. RESEARCH QUESTION
Whenever a court rules against a defendant in a typical torts case, the court (1) deter-
mines that there was harm to a third person, (2) defines a standard against which the
defendant’s behavior is to be measured, (3) determines that the defendant violated that
standard and expresses society’s disapproval, and (4) obliges the defendant to compen-
sate the plaintiff.
While classic law and economics emphasizes the extrinsic incentive created by the
obligation to pay, interpreted as a monetary sanction, a potential tortfeasor might also
be dissuaded from committing a tort by the moral intuition of not harming a third per-
son, by the tendency to adhere to a norm, or by the desire to avoid blame. In the field,
all these factors are conflated. We therefore design an experiment to disentangle these
different sources of compliance, and study their interaction. We look at both first-round
effects and the dynamic over time.
From the perspective of classic law and economics (Posner 2011; Cooter & Ulen
2012), the threat of liability is a constraint (Shavell 1980, 1987). Would-be tortfeasors
*Address correspondence to Christoph Engel, Director, Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods,
Kurt-Schumacher-Straße 10, D 53113 Bonn, Germany; email: engel@coll.mpg.de.
We gratefully acknowledge helpful comments by Giancarlo Spagnolo and by three anonymous referees, as
well as the audiences at the Conference on Empirical Legal Studies at Berkeley, the Hebrew University Law
School in Jerusalem, the Max Planck Institute for Human Development in Berlin, and the Max Planck Institute
for Research on Collective Goods at Bonn. We are most grateful to Lukas Kießling for programming the experi-
ment in zTree, and to Florian Knauth for running the experiment in the lab.
116
Journal of Empirical Legal Studies
Volume 13, Issue 1, 116–152, March 2016
are assumed to possess perfect cognitive abilities, and to be exclusively motivated by per-
sonal profit. For such an individual, the prospect of liability changes the optimization
problem. If liability is newly imposed, or if the extent of liability is changed, rational
actors exhibit a marginal reaction.
The typical situation in the field is not one individual intentionally harming
another. Another situation is much more common. A person engages in some activity
that yields a profit. But for some outsider, this activity is risky. The first individual could
reduce the risk, but this is costly. It either has an out-of-pocket cost, or it has an oppor-
tunity cost in that the first individual would have to reduce her level of activity. In such
a setting, law and economics scholars advocate legal intervention, but they do not call
for containing risk at whatever cost. Rather, they propose to hold the first individual
liable only if she has exercised less than optimal care, or has chosen a higher than opti-
mal activity level, for that matter, with the optimum defined as marginal social benefit
equalizing marginal social cost. In the world of rational choice models, the obligation to
pay damages is anticipated. Victims never have to go to court since would-be tortfeasors
exhibit the prescribed level of care, or level of activity (Shavell 1987).
This is certainly an elucidating perspective on tort law. However, it is also narrow.
If lawyers say that the defendant has been negligent, they also mean that the defendant
did not intend to damage the plaintiff. In light of prevalent moral intuitions, knowingly
imposing harm on an innocent outsider is not the same as exposing this outsider to the
risk of suffering harm. Legal doctrine distinguishes between intentional harm and inten-
tional negligence, and considers the latter to be less blameworthy. In the first situation,
detriment is certain, while it is only a possibility in the second situation. Vignette studies
demonstrate that this doctrinal distinction reflects moral intuitions of law’s subjects
(Mueller et al. 2012). Yet exposing bystanders to risk is not morally desirable or neutral.
It still is bad, only not as bad as doing so intentionally.
1
Moral intuitions do not only matter in a deontological perspective. Lately, this
observation has fueled a whole literature on the commitment effect of promises (Char-
ness & Dufwenberg 2006; Vanberg 2008; Reuben et al. 2009; Charness & Dufwenberg
2010; Ellingsen et al. 2010; Ederer & Stremitzer 2014). To the extent that the law
matches the moral intuitions of its subjects, it may reduce enforcement efforts. If the
individual cares sufficiently about her own morality, she may be willing to live up to the
legal standard even if there is no enforcement at all.
Practical court rulings combine all three components: the court defines a behav-
ioral standard; the court expresses that the defendant has violated this standard and
explains that, thereby, the defendant has violated the normative expectations of the law;
and, using this justification, the court obliges the defendant to compensate the plaintiff
for the damage she has caused. This potentially combines four motivating forces: the
individual’s intrinsic inhibition to harm a passive outsider, normativity, blame, and a
1
See only §§ 281--283 and § 302, Restatement of the Law 2d, Torts. We are not interested in, and do not study,
an alternative definition of negligence: the actor had overlooked the risk for the outsider. Legal orders also treat
deliberate exposure to harm as negligence.
117Unpacking Negligence Liability
monetary sanction. It is the purpose of this experiment to disentangle these four forces,
and to demonstrate in which ways they contribute to the forward-looking effect of negli-
gence liability.
These four motives may be independent of each other (economists would then
call them additively separable). If so, the need for enforcing liability is the smaller the
more pronounced morally grounded inhibition to impose harm, the stronger sensitivity
to normative expectations of the (legal) community, and the stronger the disciplining
effect of blame. However, intrinsic morality, normativity, blame, and sanctions may also
be substitutes. If so, legal intervention crowds out moral inhibition, at least partly
(Bowles & Polania-Reyes 2012). Or the motives may be complements: they reinforce
each other. We have reason to expect that all three motives affect the choice of activity
level. However, we do not have cogent theoretical reasons to expect these effects to be
substitutes, complements, or not to interact with each other. We therefore do not have
a directed hypothesis.
Morality is generally believed to be a personality trait. In principle, it can there-
fore not be induced ad hoc. Yet there are situations in which moral inhibition to harm
an outsider is pointless. This is the case if the participant plays against a computer. We
exploit this possibility and repeat the experiment, but replace the passive player with a
machine. Comparing these additional treatments with the main experiment, we can
find out to which degree knowing that one exposes another human individual to a risk
of severe harm is critical for the remaining effects to play themselves out.
Rational actors do not need to learn their preferences. They possess a complete
preference function. All they need is information about the environment. A typical tort
relationship is unidirectional. There is a tortfeasor and a victim.
2
The victim is passive.
Therefore, a rational actor needs no information about the victim. All she needs is
information about the prospect of gain and the risk of having to pay compensation. All
this information is available right from the start of the experiment, even if the same
potential tortfeasor repeatedly comes into a situation that exposes passive outsiders to a
risk of harm. In principle, actors guided by morality need no learning either. When
they first face the tradeoff between gain for themselves and potential harm to a victim,
they dissolve the conflict between their individual moral standard and profit according
to the weight they attach to either element of their utility. Yet the repeated experience
of being responsible for a passive outsider, of being reminded of the social optimum, of
being blamed, or of having to compensate a victim may have an additional effect in
either direction. It may be that the individual gradually overcomes the temptation of
selfishness, and aims at living up to her own moral standards, with moral expectations
of society as expressed in official statements, and becomes more and more sensitive to
the experience of having to pay damages. Or any of these forces may lose their power if
they are called upon repeatedly. This is why we repeatedly expose our participants to
the conflict between individual profit and potential harm to a passive outsider. For
2
We bracket the possibility of contributory negligence.
118 Eisenberg and Engel

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT