UNDERSTANDING CHILDREN'S RIGHTS: THEORY AND PRACTICE

Published date01 July 2006
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/j.1744-1617.2006.00093.x
Date01 July 2006
FAMILY COURT REVIEW, Vol. 44 No. 3, July 2006 350–360
© 2006 Association of Family and Conciliation Courts
Blackwell Publishing, Ltd.Oxford, UKFCREFamily Court Review1531-2445© 2006 Association of Family and Conciliation CourtsApril 2006443Original Article
Hale / UNDERSTANDING CHILDREN’S RIGHTS: THEORY AND PRACTICEFAMILY COURT REVIEW
FOURTH WORLD CONGRESS ON FAMILY LAW AND
CHILDREN’S RIGHTS
UNDERSTANDING CHILDREN’S RIGHTS: THEORY AND
PRACTICE
Brenda Hale
This article discusses the meaning of children’s rights in the context of the European Convention on Human
Rights and the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child. Both place primary responsibility for the upbringing
and education of children on their parents and families. The freedom of parents to bring up their children in their
own way is an important component of a liberal democracy founded on respect for individual differences. So if
parents believe in moderate corporal punishment as a means of educating their children in their own religious
beliefs, is the state justif‌ied in banning such punishment either in school or in the home in order to protect the
children’s rights? This article discusses the children’s rights which are protected by doing so.
Keywords:
children’s rights
;
parents’ religion
;
corporal punishment
;
European Convention on Human Rights
;
The preamble to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights proudly begins, “Whereas
recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members
of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world . . .” Article 1
starts even more emphatically, “All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.”
But then it introduces a problem for proponents of children’s rights: “They are endowed
with reason and conscience and should act towards one another in a spirit of brotherhood.
Babies too have reason and the capacity for conscience but they have not yet learned to
use them, still less to act toward one another in a spirit of brotherhood. Learning to do
these things is an important part of growing up. So what does this mean for the idea of chil-
dren’s rights? Philosophers are interested in children’s rights because they raise interesting
questions about the whole concept of rights. Can you have rights at all if you are too young
to exercise choice, when others have to enforce your rights for you, when the obligations
upon which your most essential rights depend are often vague and ill-def‌ined, and when
you are too young to have reciprocal obligations of your own? But lawyers—and judges in
particular—are interested in children’s rights because they raise legal questions which may
require binding decisions in real cases.
The Universal Declaration also states in Article 25.2 (in the context of the right to a min-
imum standard of living and social security) that “motherhood and childhood are entitled
to special care and assistance.” But the Universal Declaration is not a binding instrument.
The special needs of children have been recognized in international instruments devoted
especially to them, most notably now in the United Nations Convention on the Rights of
the Child 1989 (CRC). The CRC is binding in international law, but it has not been made
part of the domestic law of the United Kingdom as many of its obligations are drawn in

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT