Trust in parliament

Published date01 February 2017
Date01 February 2017
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1002/pa.1647
SPECIAL ISSUE PAPER
Trust in parliament*
Soren Holmberg |Staffan Lindberg |Richard Svensson
Political Science, University of Gothenburg,
Sweden
Correspondence
Staffan Lindberg, Political Science, University
of Gothenburg, Sweden.
Email: xlista@gu.se
Parliaments areor should at least bethe central rulemaking institutions in democratic
countries. If people do not have faith in the institution making the rules, it is less likely that people
live by them. Consequently, it is beneficiary if trust in parliament is high. But it is also a normative
good in itself. If the people do not trust the key institution whereby they can exercise rule by the
people over itself,democracy itself is endangered. Secondly, trust levels should be reasonably
even spread among relevant social and political groups in a society because parliament should
ideally be a nonpartisan level playing field. However, because the majority in parliament typically
chooses and sustains the acting government, one could say that legislatures in parliamentary
democracies should not be level playing fields. According to this argument, there should be
differences in trust in parliament between groups of individuals with varying political affiliations.
Supporters of the majority in parliament should be expected to have higher trust in the legislature
compared to citizens who voted for the opposition.
We test our three hypotheses on data from some 80 countries participating in World Value
Survey, either in Waves 5 or 6. We find that people in both new and established democracies
harbor lower levels of trust than an intuitive interpretation of normative theory would lead us
to expect. We also find that the attitudes of tens of thousands of citizens garnered from across
42 new and old democracies suggest that levels of average trust in groups of these societies
are not as equally distributed, as a simple reading of democratic theory would have us to believe.
In particular, individuals with a stronger interest in politics, and who are winners by the account of
the last election, have statistically substantively relevant higher average levels of trust in
parliament as an institution than do other citizens. The latter seems to us especially potentially
problematic in particular for some of the new democracies where majoritydominant parties
manage to cling on to power over several election cycles. If what we find here were generally
applicable also over several election cycles, we would expect the gap between winners and losers
to widen and sediment and potentially sow the seeds of antisystem movements opposed to
democracy. Parliament is obviously a partisan creature in the eyes of most citizens in
democracies. The level playing field idea does not fly.
1|INTRODUCTION
Parliaments areor should at least becentral decisionmaking
institutions in democratic systems. Parliaments set budgets, decide
on policies, and define the legal norms in society, and if people do
not have faith in the institution that makes these rules, it is not very
likely that people live by them. Hence, trust supposedly lowers all
forms of transaction costs associated with governing. Consequently,
it is beneficiary if trust in parliament is high. It will make the democratic
system runs more efficiently. But it is also a normative good in itself.
Any modern form of democracy is necessarily representative in
order to solve the problem of how the people should rule over itself
(e.g., Dahl, 1989, 277; Sartori, 1987, 30; Schedler, 1999). In that
context, parliament is a critical body, and if the people do not trust
the key institution whereby they can exercise rule by the people over
itself,democracy itself is endangered.
Thus, a normative hypothesissomething we hope foris that
trust in parliament should be fairly high in democratic systems. Perhaps
not 100%we do not want blind faithbut quite high in order to yield
the good outcome effects.
Furthermoreour normative Hypothesis 2trust levels should be
reasonably even spread among relevant social and political groups in a
*This joint research project was supported by the Marianne and Marcus
Wallenberg Foundation in Sweden. The authors gratefully acknowledge their
financial support (MMW2012.0215).
Received: 12 December 2016 Accepted: 30 December 2016
DOI 10.1002/pa.1647
J Public Affairs. 2017;17:e1647.
https://doi.org/10.1002/pa.1647
Copyright © 2017 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/pa 1of9

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT