A theory of reverse retirement

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12458
Published date01 September 2020
Date01 September 2020
AuthorGregory Ponthiere
J Public Econ Theory. 2020;22:16181659.wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jpet1618
|
© 2020 Wiley Periodicals LLC
Received: 19 September 2019
|
Accepted: 10 June 2020
DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12458
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
A theory of reverse retirement
Gregory Ponthiere
Université Paris Est (ERUDITE), Paris
School of Economics, Institut Universitaire
de France, Paris, France
Correspondence
Gregory Ponthiere, Paris School of
Economics, Institut Universitaire de
France, University of ParisEst (ERUDITE),
ENS, 48 Boulevard Jourdan, Office R3.66,
75014 Paris, France.
Email: gregory.ponthiere@ens.fr
Abstract
The retirement system is usually regarded as giving
a fair reward for a long working career. However,
only workers who have a sufficiently long life ben-
efit from that reward, but not workers who die
prematurely. To reexamine the fairness of retire-
ment systems under unequal lifetime, this paper
compares standard retirement (i.e., individuals work
before being retired) withhypotheticalreverse
retirement (i.e., individuals are retired before
working). We show that, under standard assump-
tions, an economy with reverse retirement, once in
place, converges towards a unique stationary equi-
librium. At the normative level, we show that, when
labor productivity declines with age, reverse retire-
ment cannot be optim al under the utilit arian cri-
terion (unlike standard retirement), whereas reverse
retirement can be optimal under the ex post egali-
tarian criterion (giving priority to the worstoff in
realized terms). Finally, we show that there exists a
set of policy instruments that allow a government to
organize a successful transition from standard to
reverse retirement.
1|INTRODUCTION
Historical roots of retirement systems are old. These date back, in England, to the Poor Laws
(1599), which included dispositions for elderly individuals unable to work. In France, an édit
royal of 1604 required mine operators to dedicate 1/30th of their output to miners in need.
However, those early retirement systems differ from modern systems, on the grounds that these
were far from universal: Poor Laws were implemented at the parish level, whereas the French
édit royal concerned only the mining industry.
1
Universal pension systems are more recent:
Bismarck's oldage insurance in Germany dates back to 1889, while Beveridge's pension system
in the UK dates back to 1942.
Retirement systems were introduced not only because of an insurance motive (protecting
individuals against the risk of being poor at the old age), but also, for redistributive reasons.
Retirement systems allow, in theory, for both vertical redistribution (frompotentially richer
active young individuals toward inactive old individuals) and horizontal redistribution (from
richer to poorer retirees thanks to nonproportional replacement rates). Distributive aspects are
key elements in the design of a fair retirement system (see Cremer & Pestieau, 2011; Schokkaert
& Van Parijs, 2003; Schokkaert, Devolder, Hindriks, & Vandenbroucke, 2017).
Studying the fairness of retirement systems raises additional difficulties when individuals differ on
longevity. In particular, an important source of injustice lies in the fact that some proportion of the
workforce dies before reaching the retirement age. For instance, in France, about 10% of men and 4%
of women die before reaching the age of 60.
2
Those people obviously do not enjoy retirement. Thus,
although the retirement system is usually presented as giving a fair reward for a long working career,
the fairness of that system can be questioned, on the grounds that only workers who have a suffi-
cientlylonglifecanbenefitfromthatreward,whereas those who die prematurely are not rewarded.
The goal of this paper is to reexamine the fairness of retirement systems in an economy
with unequal lifetime. In particular, we propose to study the capacity of retirement systems
differing in terms of the ages of entry and exit of laborto allow the society to achieve some
form of social justice despite longevity inequality.
From the perspective of social justice, a major requirement consists of compensating
disadvantages due to circumstances, that is, factors on which individuals have no control.
According to the Principle of Compensation (Fleurbaey, 2008 and Fleurbaey & Maniquet, 2004),
wellbeing inequalities due to circumstances should be abolished by governments. Given that
longevity inequalities are largely due to circumstances (e.g., the genetic background), the
Principle of Compensation applies to the case of unequal lifetime.
3
Thus that principle provides
ethical support for the compensation of prematurely dead individuals.
It is far from trivial to design retirement systems favoring the compensation of the short
lived. In a recent paper, Fleurbaey, Leroux, Pestieau, and Ponthiere (2016)examinedhow
varying the age at retirement could achieve such a compensation. Fleurbaey et al. (2016)
characterized the optimal retirement age while adopting an ex post egalitarian social wel-
fare criterion, which gives absolute priority to the worstoff in realized terms (who is, in
general, the shortlived). Fleurbaey et al. (2016) showed that the compensation of the un-
lucky shortlived pushes toward postponing retirement in comparison with the utilitarian
social optimum. The underlying intuition is that postponing retirement allows to transfer
moreresourcestowardtheyoungage,and,hence,toincreasethewellbeing of all young
individuals (including those who will turn out to die prematurely).
Although Fleurbaey et al. (2016) casts some light on how taking care about the compensation of
the shortlived can affect the optimal age at retirement, it remained based on the standard view on
retirement. Actually, Fleurbaey et al. (2016) assumed the usual life cycle, where individuals work at
1
In France, another édit royal published in 1673 created a pension for officers of the Marine Royale, while pensions were
introduced for soldiers and civil servants in, respectively, 1831 and 1853 (see Lavigne, 2013).
2
See the Human Mortality Data Base.
3
On the impact of genes on longevity inequalities, see Christensen, Johnson, and Vaupel (2006).
PONTHIERE
|
1619
the young age, and become retiree as they reach some (older) age. But can we think about
alternative retirement systems that would be more fair?
To reexamine the fairness of retirement systems under unequal lifetime, this paper pro-
poses to go beyond the standard representation of retirement systems, in which individuals are
first workers at the young age, and, then, if they survive to sufficiently high ages, retirees. We
propose to consider also what we call a reverseretirement system, where individuals would
unlike in existing societiesbe first retirees at the young age, and, then, workers at the old age.
This paper examines the conditions under which such apurely hypotheticalreverse re-
tirement system dominates the standard retirement system.
At this early stage of our explorations, it should be stressed that reverse retirement does not
exist in actual economies, and is thus a pure theoretical abstraction. Reverse retirement is a
kind of utopia,in the same way as standard retirement was regarded as an utopia during the
longest part of History. Note, however, that, in the common language, the term reverse re-
tirementrefers to the behavior of a minority of retirees who go back to work. In some sense,
the reverse retirement system that we consider is a generalization of this behavior to the entire
society. We propose to compare existing standard retirement systems with thepurely
hypotheticalreverse retirement system.
For that purpose, we develop a 4period overlapping generations model (OLG) with unequal
lifetime. That dynamic framework will allow us to examine not only the social desirability of reverse
retirement, but also, its economic feasibility. We assume that: (a) production involves physical
capital as well as young and/or old labor; (b) there is a perfect substitutability between young and
old labor (but with agedependent labor productivity); (c) older workers face a higher marginal
disutility of labor than younger workers. We first study the temporary equilibrium, and the longrun
dynamics of the economy, under either standard or reverse retirement. Those two kinds of economy
differ from a qualitative perspective: under standard retirement, young individuals work and save
for their old days (during which they will be retired), whereas, under reverse retirement, young
individuals do not work, borrow resources, and pay these back at the old age (during which they
work). In a second stage, we examine the social desirability of standard and reverse retirement
under two social welfare criteria: utilitarianism and ex post egalitarianism.
Our results are threefold. First, at a positive level, we show that, under standard assumptions on
technology and preferences, an economy with reverse retirement, once in place, converges toward a
unique stationary equilibrium. Thus an economy with reverse retirement is sustainable in the long
run. Second, at the normative level, we show that, when labor productivity declines with age,
reverse retirement is never optimal under the utilitarian criterion, but can, under some conditions,
be optimal under the ex post egalitarian criterion. From the ex post egalitarian perspective, standard
retirement dominates reverse retirement in less developed economies (characterized by harsh
working conditions, a steep ageproductivity profile and a lower probability of survival to age 50),
but reverse retirement dominates in advanced economies (characterized by less harsh working
conditions, a flatter ageproductivity profile, and a higher probability of survival to age 50). Third,
we show that, although the transition from standard to reverse retirement leads to the collapse of
the economy in the laissezfaire, there exists a set of policy instruments that allow governments to
organize a successful transition from standard to reverse retirement.
This paper is related to several branches of the literature. First, it is related to the literature on
retirement and distribution (Cremer & Pestieau, 2011;Schokkaert&VanParijs, 2003; Schokkaert
et al., 2017), which focuses on standard retirement, unlike this paper, which also examines reverse
retirement. Second, this paper is also related to the literature on fairness and compensation under
unequal lifetime (see Fleurbaey & Ponthiere, 2013; Fleurbaey et al., 2016,2014). Fleurbaey et al.
1620
|
PONTHIERE

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT