The Virtues of Everyday Talk: The Enduring Significance of John Milton’s Theory of Expressive Liberties

Date01 August 2021
DOI10.1177/0090591720966267
Published date01 August 2021
AuthorChloé Bakalar
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591720966267
Political Theory
2021, Vol. 49(4) 584 –612
© The Author(s) 2020
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/0090591720966267
journals.sagepub.com/home/ptx
Article
The Virtues of Everyday
Talk: The Enduring
Significance of John
Milton’s Theory of
Expressive Liberties
Chloé Bakalar
Abstract
The system of free expression John Milton defends in Areopagitica, a pamphlet
against prior restraint in publishing, is often characterized as merely a
proto-liberal, truth-based marketplace of ideas theory. But this represents a
misunderstanding of Milton’s views on the freedoms of conscience, speech,
and the press. The tendency in political theory, philosophy, and law to reduce
the “free speech Milton” to Areopagitica, and the reduction of that essay to
several soundbites, has meant sidelining both the significant exceptions to
expressive liberties that Milton calls for and also the role of the social in
his theory. This incomplete characterization has enabled Milton’s misuse in
First Amendment discourse and jurisprudence, where he is made to support
hierarchical approaches to free speech that privilege public political speech
and are therefore ill-equipped to address the full range of communicative
experiences. More comprehensive readings of Milton, however, reveal both
certain limits to free expression, and also deep consideration for a wide
range of speech acts. By reading Milton’s theory of expressive liberties in
light of the justifications he provides for those freedoms—i.e., virtue-building
and Truth-seeking—this essay provides a fuller account of his views. What
emerges is a distinctly Miltonian, virtue-driven “political theory of everyday
1Political Science, Temple University, Philadelphia, PA, USA
Corresponding Author:
Chloé Bakalar, Assistant Professor, Political Science, Temple University, 1115 Polett Walk,
#455, Philadelphia, PA 19122, USA.
Email: chloe.bakalar@temple.edu
966267PTXXXX10.1177/0090591720966267Political TheoryBakalar
research-article2020
Bakalar 585
talk” that locates value in even the most ordinary communicative acts.
This theory—embracing both verbal and nonverbal expression—not only
complements existing political theories of the everyday but can also help
illuminate contemporary free speech concerns, many of which stem from
the libertarian approach to expressive liberties that Milton (inadvertently)
helped inspire.
Keywords
freedom of speech, John Milton, everyday talk, censorship, virtue, expressive
liberties
And though all the windes of doctrin were let loose to play upon the earth, so
Truth be in the field, we do injuriously by licencing and prohibiting to misdoubt
her strength. Let her and Falsehood grapple; who ever knew Truth put to the
wors, in a free and open encounter?
John Milton, Areopagitica1
Freedom to “think as you will and speak as you think” enjoys unparalleled
esteem in liberal democracies.2 Expressive liberties feature at the center of
debates on political legitimacy, and lawmakers consistently conceptualize
these freedoms as fundamental rights, often placing them first and foremost
on lists of legal and human rights. But while there is broad consensus that
expressive liberties form the bedrock of liberal democracy, the variation in
how these freedoms are imagined and enacted suggests that the ideal con-
tours of freedom of conscience, speech, and the press are less clear. In the
United States, debates wage on over what expression has merit, what does
not, and the bases upon which these determinations are made. As much of
this discussion is framed in terms of legal rights, it is often bounded by that
speech deemed to be “at the heart of the First Amendment’s protections”—
namely, speech in the public sphere and/or addressing issues of clear public
importance.3 Speech concerning “matters of purely private concern,” by con-
trast, has been judged to be “of less First Amendment concern.”4 Seemingly
apolitical speech in (semi-)private spaces thus receives less consideration,
(often) less protection, and less consistent treatment.5
The lack of clarity regarding private speech—Elena Kagan once summa-
rized this jurisprudence as “largely a mess, resisting any coherent under-
standing”6—is increasingly problematic. As information technologies have
evolved alongside norms and practices that challenge the distinction between

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT