The social cost problem, rights, and the (non)empty core

Date01 April 2019
AuthorAlain Marciano,Philippe Solal,Stéphane Gonzalez
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12334
Published date01 April 2019
Received: 16 October 2017
|
Accepted: 11 August 2018
DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12334
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
The social cost problem, rights, and the
(non)empty core
Stéphane Gonzalez
1
|
Alain Marciano
2
|
Philippe Solal
1
1
Groupe danalyse et de théorie économique,
Université de SaintEtienne, SaintEtienne,
France
2
Montpellier Recherche en Économie,
Université de Montpellier, Montpellier,
France
Correspondence
Stéphane Gonzalez, Université de
SaintEtienne, CNRS, GATE LSE UMR 5824,
F42023 SaintEtienne, France.
Email: stephane.gonzalez@univ-st-etienne.fr
Funding information
Agence Nationale de Recherches, Grant/
Award Numbers: ANR11IDEX0007,
ANR10LABXll0l, ANR13BSHS10010;
Indepth UDL 2018; Programme Avenir Lyon
SaintEtienne of Université de Lyon
Abstract
We revisit the Coase theoremthrough the lens of a
cooperative game model which takes into account the
assignment of rights among agents involved in a problem
of social cost. We consider the case where one polluter
interactswithmanypotentialvictims.Givenanassign-
ment or a mapping of rights, we represent a social cost
problem by a cooperative game. A solution consists in a
payoff vector. We introduce three properties for a
mapping of rights. First, core compatibility indicates that
the core of the associated cooperative games is none-
mpty. Second, KaldorHicks core compatibility indicates
that there is a payoff vector in the core where victims are
fully compensated for the damage once the negotiations
are completed. Third, no veto power for a victim says that
novictimhasthepowertovetoanagreementsignedby
the rest of the society. We then demonstrate two main
results. First, core compatibility is satisfied if and only if
the rights are assigned either to the polluter or to the
entire set of victims. Second, there is no mapping of
rights satisfying KaldorHicks core compatibility and no
veto power for a victim.
1
|
INTRODUCTION
After George Stigler coined the term, and invented its first version (Stigler, 1966, p. 113), the Coase
theoremhas been reformulated many times, up to the point that it can be said that there does not exist one
but many Coase theorems.
1
Despite their differences, these versions can nonetheless be characterized by
J Public Econ Theory. 2019;21:347365. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jpet © 2018 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.
|
347
1
See a presentation of the different versions in Medema (2011, 2017) and Medema and Zerbe (2000).
two theses. First, the efficiency thesis according to which in the absence of transaction costs and if property
rights are well defined, agents will always bargain to reach an optimal allocation of resources; second, the
invariance or neutrality thesis according to which the outcome of bargaining is independent of the distribution
of rights. Thus, strictly speaking, it can be said the Coase theorem holds if both theses are verified
simultaneously.
Around these theses, a particularly important literature developed and the theorem was refined in many
directions. Attempts were made to generalize itin particular because Ronald Coase, in The Problem of
Social Cost" (1960), reasoned with two agents onlyor to demonstrate under whichconditions it is verified
because of its assumption of zero transaction costs. The models were then developed in terms of competitive
equilibrium (e.g., Chipman & Tian, 2012; Hurwicz, 1995), (perfect) Nash equilibrium of a strategic/bargaining
game (e.g., Anderlini & Felli, 2001, 2006; Ellingsen & Paltseva, 2016; Lee & Sabourian, 2007), of the
nonemptiness of the core of a cooperative game (e.g., Aivazian & Callen, 1981; Aivazian, Callen, &
Lipnowski, 1987; Ambec & Kervinio, 2016; Coase, 1981; Shapley & Shubik, 1969). In this paper, we also adopt
a cooperative approach. Itdiffersfromtheabovementioned works in that we provide necessary and
sufficient conditions under which the assignment of rights between groups of agents leads to a
nonempty core.
1.1
|
The model
We consider a large class of social cost problems between a finite set of potential victims and only one
polluter; transaction costs are supposed to be equal to zero. The activity of the polluter creates damage that
affects the victims. We propose to describe this damage by nondecreasing functions on the set of activity
levels of the polluter. In a similar manner, the benefit function of the polluter is assumed to be nondecreasing
on his or her set of activity levels. Hence, unsurprisingly, the victims and the polluter have conflicting
interests.
The payoffs that agents may or will receive after these conflicts are solved are obviously shaped by the law that
preexists and frames economic and social interactions. But they are not given by or specified in the law. The law,
general and abstract, applies to the whole set of social cost problems, which means that it specifies how a problem
of social cost, in abstract terms, should be treatedwho can negotiate and with whombut does not say what
should be the payoffs to a specific social cost problem. This is decided by the parties in the negotiation. In other
words, because it shapes interactions between (groups) of agents, the law affects how these (groups) of individuals
will negotiate with each other but does not specify the individual payoffs that will result from the negotiation. Thus,
the law also gives the parties a certain leeway to negotiate a binding agreement to the specific problem of social
cost in which they can be involved.
The negotiation, which takes place between the polluter and the victims, aims at signing a binding
agreement about how much activity the polluter will be allowed to undertakethat is, how much pollution he
is authorized to generateand how much agents are compensated. For their part, the victims may gather
themselves in coalitions to negotiate with the polluter. And monetary transfers can be freely made within a
coalition.
The possibility or permission granted to any group of agents who want to form a coalition with the purpose a
binding agreement with the polluter corresponds to what we call a right. That right, to be more precise, gives the
possibility to a coalition to select the best contract for itself. Obviously, a large number of coalitions of agents can
have the right to decide the level of production of the polluter, as well as how much compensation its members will
receive. The set of all the possible rights granted to the polluter and victims form what we call a mapping or an
assignment of rights.
In our model, we impose s ome reasonable condition s on the mappings of rights. Firs t, independence:
A mapping of rights is independent from the respective benefi t and damage functions of the indivi duals involved
348
|
GONZALEZ ET AL.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT