The Rights of Woman and the Equal Rights of Men

DOI10.1177/0090591720946310
Date01 June 2021
Published date01 June 2021
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591720946310
Political Theory
2021, Vol. 49(3) 403 –430
© The Author(s) 2020
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/0090591720946310
journals.sagepub.com/home/ptx
Article
The Rights of Woman
and the Equal Rights
of Men
Karen Green1
Abstract
While standard histories of Western political thought represent women’s
rights as an offshoot of the earlier movement for the equal rights of men,
this essay argues that the eighteenth-century push for democracy and
equal rights was grounded in arguments first used to defend women’s
right to moral and religious self-determination, based on their rational
and spiritual equality with men. In tandem with the rise of critiques
of absolute monarchy, ideal marriage, which had previously involved
lordship and subjection, was transformed into an equal companionate
relationship based on inclination and affection. The essay argues that the
transformation, by the time of the American and French revolutions, of
neo-Roman republicanism—which had been aristocratic and oligarchic—
into egalitarian, democratic republicanism had been mediated by the
extension of arguments, widely distributed in the literature criticizing the
slavery of marriage, into a general critique of slavery and support for the
equal rights of men.
Keywords
republicanism, democracy, political liberty, marriage, monarchy
1Associate Professor, School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, University of Melbourne,
Melbourne, Victoria, Australia
Corresponding Author:
Karen Green, Associate Professor, School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, University
of Melbourne, 3/51 Robe St, St Kilda 3182, Melbourne, Victoria 3010, Australia.
Email: karen.green@unimelb.edu.au
946310PTXXXX10.1177/0090591720946310Political TheoryGreen
research-article2020
404 Political Theory 49(3)
Introduction
A popular view of the history of political thought represents feminism as a
late eighteenth-century development and an adaptation of the theory of the
equal rights of men. A characteristic statement is found in Anthony C.
Grayling’s Towards the Light in a chapter on “Slaves, Workers, Women,”
The story of the struggle for women’s rights goes back to isolated but
remarkable voices in the seventeenth century and before . . . but the first major
feminist voice belongs to Mary Wollstonecraft, whose A Vindication of the
Rights of Woman marks an epoch in the cause.1
Coming after the French declaration of the rights of man, Wollstonecraft’s
tract, like Olympe de Gouges’s Les droits de la femme, is taken to represent a
decisive turn, extending a tradition of political philosophy, which previously
had nothing to do with them, to include women.2 Influential feminist histori-
ans have also accepted that the doctrine of abstract universal rights was devel-
oped by men and have therefore questioned its validity in the face of bodily
difference.3 Grayling’s history of the rise of liberty charts the defense of reli-
gious toleration through the works of Desiderius Erasmus, Sebastian Castellio,
John Milton, and John Locke. He does mention marriage, and he implies that
it is Milton’s 1644 defense of divorce that stands at the origin of the later trans-
formation of marriage from a contract for reproduction to a bond of compan-
ionship.4 Women only enter the story with Wollstonecraft, so that earlier
women’s literary and political interventions must be presumed to have been as
ineffectual as Simone de Beauvoir assumed, when she dismissed earlier
female defenders of women as “isolated individuals” who had “protested
against the harshness of their destiny” but were unable to achieve anything
without male authorization.5
Women are even more thoroughly absent from Quentin Skinner’s influen-
tial Foundations of Modern Political Thought. He highlights the masculinity
of the early Italian republics and explains how Cicero’s representation of
virtus as the highest kind of excellence, along with his emphasis on the need
for rhetoric to instruct and incite virtue, is extolled by Petrarch and results in
the revival of the vir virtutis. Augustine’s insistence on humanity’s sinful
nature and incapacity to deserve grace, so dominant during the medieval
period, comes to be replaced with a new renaissance optimism that virtue and
excellence can and should be achieved in this world, through the acquisition
of “honour, glory and worldly fame.”6 Skinner’s second volume, like
Grayling’s, traces reformation developments, through Martin Luther and
John Calvin to George Buchanan, focusing on Protestant challenges to the

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT