The Effects of Ideology on Federal Trial Judges' Decisions to Admit Scientific Expert Testimony

AuthorJeremy Buchman
Published date01 September 2007
Date01 September 2007
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/1532673X07302339
Subject MatterArticles
American Politics Research
Volume 35 Number 5
September 2007 671-693
© 2007 Sage Publications
10.1177/1532673X07302339
http://apr.sagepub.com
hosted at
http://online.sagepub.com
671
Author’s Note: Earlier versions of this article were presented at the 2004 meeting of the
Midwest Political Science Association annual meeting, Chicago, IL and the 2004 meeting of
the American Political Science Association annual meeting,Chicago, IL. The author wishes to
thank editor James Gimpel, Lawrence Baum, Paul Brace, Anke Grosskopf, Melinda Gann
Hall, David Klein, and the anonymous reviewers for their instructive feedback at various
stages of this article. All errors remain the responsibility of the author.
The Effects of Ideology on
Federal Trial Judges’
Decisions to Admit
Scientific Expert Testimony
Jeremy Buchman
Long Island University
This article examines trial court rulings concerning the admissibility of scientific
expert testimony. In Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals (1993), the
Supreme Court reaffirmed the trial judge’s role as a “gatekeeper” and gave trial
judges substantial discretion over their scrutiny of expert testimony. Because the
external constraints on admissibility rulings are minimal, one might expect that
if trial judges’ideology were to play some role in their decision making, it might
do so here. To test this expectation,I perform a binomial logit analysis of federal
district court Daubert rulings in tort cases from 1983 to 2003. I find substantial
support for the claim that trial judges’ ideology can predict decisions on
admissibility. I find less support, however, for the claim that Daubert affected
trial judges’ willingness to admit such testimony, and no evidence that such
decisions are affected by the prospect of reversal on appeal.
Keywords: judicial behavior; trial courts; political ideology; Daubert
rulings; admissibility of evidence; judicial discretion
Section 1: Introduction
Since the dawn of the behavioralist movement, scholars of judicial
behavior have split on the question of what role ideology plays in explain-
ing judicial, and especially U.S. Supreme Court, decision making. The
perspective that assigns the greatest weight to ideology, the attitudinal
672 American Politics Research
model, has seen its rise to prominence met by a steady stream of criticism
for its portrayal of judicial behavior. Legal practitioners and some legal
scholars have faulted the model for presenting a depiction of Supreme
Court decision making that conflicts strongly with the justices’ perceptions
of their own actions, and in particular for rendering irrelevant such factors
as commitment to a theory of interpretation and respect for precedent. The
scholars most closely identified with the attitudinal model, Jeffrey Segal
and Harold Spaeth (1993; 2002; Spaeth & Segal, 1999), respond by assert-
ing that the traditional legal model, defined in terms of fidelity to case facts
viewed “in light of the plain meaning of statutes and the Constitution, the
intent of the Framers, and/or precedent” (Segal & Spaeth, 2002, p. 48), does
not qualify as a model at all because it lacks falsifiability. Because theories
of textual interpretation fail to produce determinate outcomes across cases,
and precedents can be manipulated so as to provide ostensible support to
either side of a legal dispute, the legal model can justify any outcome and,
as such, lacks explanatory value (Segal & Spaeth, 2002, pp. 48-84; Spaeth
& Segal, 1999, p. xv). According to behavioralists, the justices’policy pref-
erences can explain the bulk of Supreme Court decision making not only on
the merits but also at the certiorari stage.
Among political scientists who study judicial behavior, the attitudinal
model’s emphasis on the influence of unconstrained policy preferences has
been challenged from two broad directions. In one camp are rational choice
theorists who accept the attitudinalists’ assumption of policy-maximizing
behavior but reject the claim that the justices are, in practice, unconstrained
in their ability to further their policy preferences. Instead, the justices must
calibrate their behavior so as to account for the preferences of other actors,
be they fellow justices (see, e.g., Epstein & Knight, 1998; Maltzman,
Spriggs, & Wahlbeck, 2000) or the elected branches of the national gov-
ernment (see, e.g., Ferejohn & Shipan, 1990; Gely & Spiller, 1990, 1992;
Rogers, 2001). In the second camp are “new institutionalists” (Smith, 1988)
who challenge attitudinal approaches on several fronts. Justices might
indeed hold policy preferences, but they also might feel an obligation to
uphold certain norms and expectations with respect to what conforms to
proper judicial behavior (see, e.g., Gillman, 2001; Gillman & Clayton,
1999, p. 5). In this conception, the constraints faced by judges are not lim-
ited to those imposed by external actors; they also include internally
imposed strictures. Viewed in a different light, the relationship between
judges and institutional arrangements is a two-way street: “Judicial behav-
ior is not merely structured by institutions but is also constituted by them
in the sense that the goals and values associated with particular political

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT