THE CASE FOR INSINCERITY

Date11 June 2003
Published date11 June 2003
Pages143-164
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(03)29006-2
AuthorJohn M Kang
THE CASE FOR INSINCERITY
John M. Kang
ABSTRACT
Much of the philosophical debate between religionists and secularists has
focused on whether to permit people to invoke publicly religious arguments
to justify their position on laws and policies. There is a question related to
this debate whose answer is often regarded by both liberals and religionists
as intuitive and straightfoward: May religionists offer secular justifications
in the public square to support or oppose laws and policies without sincerely
accepting such reasons as consistent with their respective religion? Some
religionists and especially some prominent liberals tend to answer in the
negative, disdaining the thought of embracing an alternative that seems
duplicitious. I argue that such negative responses tend to neglect the value
of insincerity in public justifications.
1. INTRODUCTION
Much of the philosophical debate between religionists and secularists has focused
on whether to permit people to invoke publicly religious arguments to justify
their position on laws and policies. Prominent liberals like Robert Audi, Kent
Greenawalt and John Rawls argue that in some instances, people should abstain
from both invoking religious arguments in the public square and from consulting
religious sources alone in arriving at judgment,1while religionists like Michael
Perry,Nicholas Wolterstorffand StephenCarter assert thatreligionists bepermitted
greater freedom in both areas.2
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society,Volume 29, 143–164
Copyright © 2003 by Elsevier Science Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/PII: S1059433703290062 143
144 JOHN M. KANG
There is a question related to this debate whose answer is often regarded by
both liberals and religionists as intuitive and straightforward. The question is
this: May religionists offer secular justifications in the public square to support or
oppose laws and policies without sincerely accepting such reasons as consistent
with their respective religion? Some religionists and especially some liberals tend
to answer in the negative, disdaining the thought of embracing an alternative that
seems duplicitous. Liberals have leveled sustained criticism against the thought
of such insincerity by religionists in public discourse. Kent Greenawalt labels
such insincerity “deceitful” and “dishonest” (Greenawalt, 1995, p. 163); Robert
Audi derides it as “manipulative” and its propensity “a moral defect” (Audi,
2000, pp. 110, 128); and John Rawls rebukes it as “hypocritical” (Rawls, 1996,
p. 215). These liberals’ critical responses find systematic expression in formal
objections stemming from “consequence” and from “fairness.”3The former
asserts that insincerity by religionists leads to negative results like alienation
or civil strife, while the latter holds that it violates a principle of equal respect
which insists that people be entitled to rational justifications for coercive laws or
policies.
In this essay, I respond to these liberals’ objections from the perspective of
liberalism itself and not from some other political ideology. In doing so, I will not
challenge the purposes animating the fairness and consequence objections which
I regard as consistent with the broad aspirations of liberalism. While specific
conceptions of the fairness and consequence objections are debatable, I think it
apparent that the concerns driving both are reasonable in the abstract, and that
what’s generally at issue in fair-minded people isn’t their intrinsic value, but the
scope and depth of their meaning and application. Indeed, it’s telling that even
regimes or groups that undermine equal respect or civic harmony often justify
their actions to the public in terms of such values. So instead of critiquing the
premises of either objection, I argue that sincerity is at best irrelevant and at worse
harmful in achieving either good consequences or fairness between religionists
and secularists.
As for my method, it derives from a response to highly idealized accounts by
someliberalsabout theduty forsincerity.Their arguments,Ishow,are insufficiently
attentive to political context. They derive a duty for sincerity from vague notions
of fairness, unrealistic expectations for civic virtue, or from some hypothetically
idealized condition. I juxtapose these approaches to politics as practiced to show
that the objections to insincerity rest on impractical premises that fail to generate
workable standards. By this, I do not mean to suggest that I plan to marshal
hard empirical evidence; rather, I seek to write from the perspective that political
differences often are not amenable to open discussion, for the worldviews from
which they derive are sometimes incompatible and mutually resistant.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT