The Alternative to Utopia Is Myopia*

AuthorBoaventura de Sousa Santos
Published date01 December 2020
Date01 December 2020
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/0032329220962644
Subject MatterSpecial Issue Articles
https://doi.org/10.1177/0032329220962644
Politics & Society
2020, Vol. 48(4) 567 –584
© The Author(s) 2020
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/0032329220962644
journals.sagepub.com/home/pas
Special Issue Article
The Alternative to
Utopia Is Myopia*
Boaventura de Sousa Santos
University of Coimbra (Portugal)
Abstract
This essay, written in memory of Erik Olin Wright (1947–2019), considers Wright’s
project of constructing and identifying real utopias. It confronts a tension in Wright’s
oeuvre, the question of the knowledge by means of which reformers can identify the
utopias that ground the really existing real utopias.
Keywords
utopias, Erik Olin Wright, Marx
Corresponding Author:
Boaventura de Sousa Santos, University of Coimbra (Portugal), Colégio S. Jerónimo, Largo D. Dinis,
Apartado 3087, Coimbra, 3000-995, Portugal.
Email: bsantos@ces.uc.pt
*This essay is part of a special issue of Politics & Society celebrating and examining the life and work of
longtime board member Erik Olin Wright (1947–2019).
962644PASXXX10.1177/0032329220962644Politics & SocietySantos
research-article2020
568 Politics & Society 48(4)
Ideologically speaking, the twentieth century was hostile to the idea of utopia, even
though there were several bouts of utopia-oriented political practices, such as the first
years of the Russian Revolution, the Cultural Revolution in China, the first years of the
Cuban Revolution, and the student revolts in the late 1960s, starting with May 1968.
In spite of all this, the idea of dystopia fared much better in mass culture than the idea
of utopia. In the social sciences, both bourgeois and Marxist science, however, ostra-
cized utopia, for different reasons. Marxist hostility to utopia stemmed from Marx
himself and was clearly expressed in 1847 in The Poverty of Philosophy (written in
French),1 whereas the bourgeois social sciences were developed in part against the
French utopian socialism of the late nineteenth century and were later much influ-
enced by the liberal thinkers of the 1950s and 1960s, such as Karl Popper and Isaiah
Berlin.2
In the first part of his intellectual trajectory, Erik Olin Wright was a brilliant repre-
sentative of the antiutopian Marxist tradition. The hostility to utopia was most tellingly
present in the work of the “non-bullshit Marxist group,” inspired by G.A. Cohen and
analytical philosophy, to which Wright belonged together with Jon Elster, John
Roemer, Adam Przeworski, and Robert Brenner.3 In the second part of his intellectual
trajectory, Wright became increasingly interested in the question of the political will in
social transformation. He became convinced that the visions of an ideal society were
the necessary guides of pragmatically possible political practices against oppression.4
Long before him, Max Weber had claimed in Politics as a Vocation that “certainly all
historical experience confirms the truth—that man would not have attained the possi-
ble unless time and again he had reached out for the impossible.”5 In 2010, Wright
wrote the following in the overview of the Real Utopias Project:
The Real Utopia Project embraces this tension between dreams and practice. It is founded
on the belief that what is pragmatically possible is not fixed independently of our
imaginations, but is itself shaped by our visions. . . . Nurturing clear-sighted understandings
of what it would take to create social institutions free of oppression is part of creating a
political will for radical social changes to reduce oppression. . . . What we need, then, are
“real utopias”: utopian ideals that are grounded in the real potentials of humanity, utopian
destinations that have accessible waystations, utopian designs of institutions that can
inform our practical tasks of muddling through in a world of imperfect conditions for
social change.6
This shift caused some tension in the Marxist social science Wright continued to
espouse. In the afterword to Wright’s posthumous book, Michael Burawoy summa-
rizes what he calls “the conundrum of Wright’s oeuvre”: “namely his move from
class analysis without utopias to utopias without class analysis.”7 Thus formulated,
this conundrum raises the question, Who needs utopia? In this essay, I argue that
before answering, it is necessary to confront another tension in Wright’s oeuvre, the
question of the knowledge by means of which we can identify the utopias that ground
the really existing real utopias. In other words, What counts as a radical understanding
of society?

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT