The Aesthetic Habermas: Communicative Power and Judgment

AuthorGlenn Mackin
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/00905917221092412
Published date01 October 2022
Date01 October 2022
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/00905917221092412
Political Theory
2022, Vol. 50(5) 780 –808
© The Author(s) 2022
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/00905917221092412
journals.sagepub.com/home/ptx
Article
The Aesthetic Habermas:
Communicative Power
and Judgment
Glenn Mackin1
Abstract
Since the publication of Between Facts and Norms, Habermas’s concept of
communicative power has been the topic of significant discussion. This
article contributes to this conversation by examining Habermas’s account of
what makes communication powerful. I argue that Habermas’s conception
of communicative power describes a nonviolent and noninstrumental mode
of acting and being with others in language. This mode of engagement
underwrites a conception of power that is structurally different from
willing, one that builds meaningful worlds and (trans-)forms those engaging
in communicative procedures. In drawing out this aspect of Habermas’s
conception, I show that he is not a rationalist and proceduralist whose
account of communicative procedures protects decision-making from
irrational aesthetic powers. Rather, he presents communication as a mimetic
achievement, a set of aesthetic practices and experiences that affectively
alter its participants. With this position, Habermas makes an important
contribution to and not just against the analysis of the aesthetic dimensions of
political life. In casting communication as a mimetic achievement, Habermas
presents an account of how communication opens worlds and forms
subjects. Yet since these aspects of communication arrive in linguistic form,
he can also examine affective and aesthetic experiences within discursive
procedures. We can understand world-opening and aesthetic (trans-)
1Chair, Humanities Department, Associate Professor of Political Science, Eastman School of
Music, Rochester, NY, USA
Corresponding Author:
Glenn Mackin, Chair, Humanities Department, Associate Professor of Political Science,
Eastman School of Music, 26 Gibbs Street, Rochester, NY 14604-2505, USA.
Email: gmackin@esm.rochester.edu
1092412PTXXXX10.1177/00905917221092412Political TheoryMackin
research-article2022
Mackin 781
formation as an essential part of democratic politics while also identifying
the perspectives and resources by which actors can reflect on and critically
evaluate whether an opinion is justified or whether a political project is
worth pursuing.
Keywords
Habermas, communicative power, mimesis, communicative rationality,
democratic theory
Habermas actually pursues a sublation of rationality and mimesis, where
communicative rationality, rightly put, is a theory of rational illumination or,
better, articulate mimesis.
--Gregg Miller (2011, 31)
Since the publication of Between Facts and Norms, Habermas’s concept of
“communicative power” has been a significant topic of discussion (cf. Günther
1996; Preuß 1996). Critics have raised questions about the ambiguities of the
concept (Flynn 2004), about whether communicative power can successfully
steer administrative systems (Reunanen and Kunelius 2020), and about
whether Habermas’s efforts to distinguish communicative power from social
power are successful (Allen 2012; O’Mahony 2010). More radically—and
this is the argument I focus on—Linda Zerilli (2016) rejects the concept on the
grounds that Habermas presents communicative power as a will. This leads
Habermas to view politics through the lens of command-obedience relations
and leaves him unable to affirm the pluralism and nonsovereign exercises of
freedom that he identifies as central to democracy (Zerilli 2016, 189). This
critique may be controversial, but Zerilli’s interpretation is not. The broad
consensus is that the distinguishing feature of communicative power is only
that it originates from rational communicative procedures. Qua power, how-
ever, communicative power is a will that functions like any other.1 It forms
and directs decisions about political projects, including constitutions, lawmak-
ing, and policies (Habermas 1996a, 151ff).
1. This tendency to equate communicative power with a political will is promi-
nent in Hugh Baxter’s (2011) argument that Habermas should dispense with the
idea of the lifeworld and should instead understand the political system in terms
of autopoiesis. The distinction between system and lifeworld, Baxter argues, is
connected to a defensive “crisis model,” where the lifeworld only defends itself
from the incursions of administrative and economic systems. Moreover, Baxter

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT