Not Subjects of the Market, but Subject to the Market: Capitalist Slavery as Expropriation

Published date01 December 2023
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/00905917231182376
AuthorMichael Gorup
Date01 December 2023
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/00905917231182376
Political Theory
2023, Vol. 51(6) 981 –1007
© The Author(s) 2023
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/00905917231182376
journals.sagepub.com/home/ptx
Article
Not Subjects of the
Market, but Subject to
the Market: Capitalist
Slavery as Expropriation
Michael Gorup1
Abstract
This essay draws political theory into dialogue with recent work in
economic history and the history of capitalism to develop an account of
the unique injustice produced by capitalist slavery in the antebellum United
States. Prevailing approaches to thinking about slavery in political theory
tend to disembed it from its broader socioeconomic context, which has
led theorists to overlook some of the distinctive horrors associated with
capitalist slavery in particular. In response, I develop a theory of capitalist
slavery as expropriation, conceived as violent domination harnessed to the
imperatives of capital accumulation. Capitalist slavery-as-expropriation
encompasses two analytically distinct moments: the moment of confiscation,
in which human lives and capacities are enclosed via commodification, and
the moment of conscription, in which enslaved labor is mobilized via routine
violence. Though enslaved people were not market subjects, this framework
reveals the extent to which they were nevertheless subject to the market.
Keywords
slavery, capitalism, domination, social death, Karl Marx, Frederick Douglass
1Assistant Professor of Political Science, New College of Florida, Sarasota, FL, USA
Corresponding Author:
Michael Gorup, Assistant Professor of Political Science, New College of Florida, 5800 Bay
Shore Road, Sarasota, FL 34243-2101, USA.
Email: mgorup@ncf.edu
1182376PTXXXX10.1177/00905917231182376Political TheoryGorup
research-article2023
982 Political Theory 51(6)
1. Though, see the growing body of literature that aims to develop a republican
account of structural domination, on which I draw (Cicerchia 2022; Gourevitch
2013; Gourevitch forthcoming; Hasan 2021; Roberts 2022).
The being of slavery, its soul and body, lives and moves in the chattel principle,
the property principle, the bill of sale principle; the cart-whip, starvation, and
nakedness, are its inevitable consequences.
—James W. C. Pennington ([1849] 2005)
For an institution that is supposed to be long dead, slavery continues to play
a conspicuous role in contemporary American politics. Recent scholarship
has revealed the “peculiar institution” to have enjoyed a disturbingly vibrant
afterlife, shaping the development of U.S. politics and society well beyond its
formal abolition in 1865. Its spectral presence can today still be detected in
the basics of constitutional design (Waldstreicher 2010), patterns of contem-
porary political behavior (Acharya, Blackwell, and Sen 2018), and the persis-
tence of racialized inequality (O’Connell 2012). It also continues to haunt our
political language. To this day, slavery represents the summum malum of
much political thinking—marking the absolute nadir of injustice, unfreedom,
and abjection. Disagree as they might about what concepts like justice, free-
dom, or equality mean, academics and ordinary citizens alike can nonetheless
agree that slavery must represent their opposite.
But this agreement begins to come undone once we shift from merely
naming slavery’s wrongness to explaining it. In political theory, there are
two prominent views worth considering. For neo-republicans, slavery is
the paradigm example of domination. It is in opposition to this image of
slavery-as-domination that contemporary republican thinkers such as Philip
Pettit (1999, 2013) and Quentin Skinner (2009) have developed their signa-
ture conception of freedom as nondomination. “The condition of liberty,”
Pettit (1999, 31) writes, “is explicated as the status of someone who, unlike
the slave, is not subject to the arbitrary power of another.” Domination, on
this view, refers to an uncontrolled power of interference held by one person
or group over another. Importantly, domination is conceived as a relationship
that obtains between agents, who may be individual persons or collectivities
but cannot be structures or systems.1 According to neo-republicans, slavery
represents an extreme form of personal domination wherein one person (ser-
vus) is entirely dependent on the uncontrolled will of another (dominus). A
benevolent master is no less a dominator than a cruel one—what matters is
the power an agent possesses, not how they wield it.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT