Stare (In)decisis: The Elusive Role of Precedent in Originalist Theory & Practice

AuthorNicholas Iacono
PositionJ.D., Georgetown University Law Center, 2022; B.A., Georgetown University, 2012
Pages389-426
NOTES
Stare (In)decisis: The Elusive Role of Precedent in
Originalist Theory & Practice
NICHOLAS IACONO*
ABSTRACT
Marginalized for decades as a frivolous theory, originalism has become the
predominant interpretive philosophy on the nation’s highest court. With the
confirmation of Justice Amy Coney Barrett, the Supreme Court now boasts a
four member originalistplurality. While this is certainly a positive develop-
ment for constitutional jurisprudence, originalism’s ascendancy has brought a
much-debated question to the fore. How should the faithful originalist judge
contend with erroneous or atextualprecedents? That is, deep-rooted legal
precedents based on interpretations that exceed, contradict, or ignore the
Constitution’s original meaning. Originalist scholars and jurists remain deeply
divided on this question. Some argue that judges must always overturn atextual
precedents regardless of the consequences, while others maintain that the ju-
dicial powerof Article III allows judges to follow atextual precedents under
certain conditions. Indeed, this issue looms large over the Court’s upcoming
abortion decisions challenging the validity of Roe v. Wade. This Note seeks to
encourage further discussion on this critical question by assessing the compet-
ing originalist views on stare decisis and exploring the distinct positions on
stare decisis embraced by the Supreme Court’s four originalists: Justices
Thomas, Gorsuch, Kavanaugh, and Barrett. In this piece, I argue that while
originalist judges should overturn atextual precedents, Article III may give
judges the power to preserve certain erroneous precedents that have fostered
longstanding economic and property-based reliance interests.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 390
I. STARE DECISIS IN ORIGINALIST THEORY. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 392
A. Strong Presumption of Validity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 392
*J.D., Georgetown University Law Center, 2022; B.A., Georgetown University, 2012. I would like to
sincerely thank Professor Keith Whittington for sharing invaluable input and feedback on this Note and for
his Constitutional Originalismseminar that encouraged me to explore this important topic. Furthermore, I
am grateful to Professor Randy Barnett for encouraging thoughtful dialogue on originalism and
constitutional interpretation at Georgetown Law. I also thank the staff of the Georgetown Journal of Law &
Public Policy for their diligence and care in helping to edit this piece. © 2022, Nicholas Iacono.
389
B. Intermediate Approaches to Precedent. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 394
C. The Stare Decisis Skeptics: No Precedent Above Original
Meaning . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 400
1. Rebutting Textual Justifications for Stare Decisis . . . . . . 400
2. Responding to the Consequentialist & Reliance-Based
Critiques. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 404
a. State Action & the Article V Amendment Process . . . 404
b. Delayed Effect of Judicial Orders . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 405
c. Grandfathering & Gravitational Force . . . . . . . . . . 405
d. Recognizing Individualized Reliance Claims . . . . . . 406
e. Gradual Restoration of Original Meaning . . . . . . . . 407
II. STARE DECISIS IN ORIGINALIST JUDICIAL PRACTICE . . . . . . . . . . . . 408
A. Justice Barrett on Precedent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 408
B. Justice Kavanaugh on Precedent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 410
C. Justice Gorsuch on Precedent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 410
D. Justice Thomas on Precedent. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 412
E. Conclusions & Practical Implications: Predictions for a
Plurality-Originalist Court . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 413
III. CRITICAL ASSESSMENT: WHAT ROLE SHOULD PRECEDENT PLAY? . 421
CONCLUSION. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 425
INTRODUCTION
Once dismissed as a fringe ideology, the last thirty years have witnessed an
explosion in the prominence of originalism
1
as a prevailing theory of constitu-
tional interpretation. The popular interest and scholarly debate fueling original-
ism’s rise have been driven, in large part, by the growing number of state and
federal judges embracing originalist methods. Recently, the confirmation of
1. Originalism has many variants, including original intent originalism, original methods
originalism, and original public meaning originalism. Unless stipulated otherwise, discussion of
originalismin this Note refers to original public meaning originalism, which posits that [t]he
Constitution means what a hypothetical reasonable observer at the time of its ratification, in possession
of all relevant information, would have understood it to mean.Gary Lawson, Mostly Unconstitutional:
The Case Against Precedent Revisited, 5 AVE MARIA L. REV. 1, 14 (2007).
390 THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW & PUBLIC POLICY [Vol. 20:389
Justice Amy Coney Barrett to the U.S. Supreme Court has once again thrust the
much-misunderstood theory into the national spotlight. As has become standard
in confirmation battles, Justice Barrett faced intense questioning regarding the
doctrine of stare decisis
2
and the validity of controversial precedents concerning
abortion rights, same-sex marriage, and healthcare. These tense exchanges
hearken to a yet unsettled debate that continues to rage within originalist dis-
course. As one scholar notes: [t]oday, the biggest single challenge facing origi-
nalists is reconciling originalism with precedent.
3
What is the originalist judge
to do when she encounters a demonstrably-erroneous precedent, i.e., a prior judi-
cial opinion that clearly violates the original meaning of the Constitution?
4
Does
fidelity to original meaning always require reversal, or does the Constitution per-
mitperhaps even requireadherence to erroneous precedent under certain cir-
cumstances? With the Court now hosting a plurality of four self-described
originalists, a reexamination of stare decisis’s place in originalist theory is timely
and consequential. Indeed, one can hardly evaluate the impact that a majority-
originalist Court will have on the nation’s legal landscape without a thorough
consideration of this issue.
5
This Note will contribute to this discussion by assessing the varied positions on
stare decisis within originalist theory and practice. Part I will trace the academic
views on precedent in originalist scholarship, noting some unsettled questions
raised by these theories. Part II will examine the positions on stare decisis taken
by the Court’s four originalists, noting how these views compare and contrast
with the theories outlined in Part I. Part II will conclude with the prediction that,
given the considerable reliance interests at stake, it is unlikely that the Court’s
originalist plurality will completely overturn key precedents related to abortion
and same-sex marriage. Part III will critically assess the prevailing theories, argu-
ing that the Court’s Article III judicial [p]ower,
6
as it was originally understood
at Ratification, incorporates the authority to preserve erroneous precedents where
substantial economic and property-based reliance interests are implicated.
2. For the purpose of this Note, stare decisis refers to the doctrine that the Supreme Court must
adhere to its own prior decisions on matters of constitutional interpretation, absent substantially
compelling reasons to overturn them.
3. Randy E. Barnett, Trumping Precedent with Original Meaning: Not as Radical as It Sounds, 22
CONST. COMMENT. 257, 258 (2005); see also Lee J. Strang, An Originalist Theory of Precedent: The
Privileged Place of Originalist Precedent, 2010 BYU L. REV. 1729, 1729 (2010) (However, busied
with building and defending originalism, originalists have thus far failed to fully explain the role of
precedent in constitutional interpretation.).
4. Unless stated otherwise, precedentin this Note refers to the horizontal precedents of the U.S.
Supreme Court concerning matters of constitutional interpretation. Furthermore, erroneousor
atextualprecedent refers to a prior Supreme Court decision, which, in the opinion of the originalist
justice, is based on an interpretive reasoning that cannot be reconciled with the original public meaning
of the constitutional text.
5. See Barnett, supra note 3, at 26970 (Knowing the degree to which a commitment to originalism
entails the rejection of the doctrine of precedent may well influence the degree to which originalism is
deemed acceptable by academics, judges, and the general public.).
6. U.S. CONST. art. III, § 1.
2022] ROLE OF PRECEDENT IN ORIGINALIST THEORY & PRACTICE 391

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT