Social welfare, parental altruism, and inequality

Published date01 September 2020
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12429
Date01 September 2020
AuthorPietro Reichlin
J Public Econ Theory. 2020;22:13911419. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jpet © 2020 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.
|
1391
Received: 9 August 2018
|
Accepted: 16 January 2020
DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12429
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
Social welfare, parental altruism, and
inequality
Pietro Reichlin
1,2
1
Department of Economics and Finance,
LUISS G. Carli, Rome, Italy
2
CEPR, London, UK
Correspondence
Pietro Reichlin, Department of Economics
and Finance, LUISS G. Carli,
Viale Romania 32, 00197 Rome, Italy.
Email: preichlin@luiss.it
Abstract
When individuals have heterogeneous and persistent
degrees of onesided parental altruism, inequality
may grow large and standard social welfare criteria
are problematic. If the planner selects Pareto optimal
allocations based on some target level of consump-
tion inequality, the solution implies an aggregation of
individuals' utilities that is strongly asymmetric and
biased toward the less altruistic dynasties. If instead,
the planner uses a symmetric utilitarian criterion, the
solution is likely to generate a large degree of long
run inequality (even relative to laissezfaire competi-
tive equilibria), it can only be decentralized with
negative estate taxes or lower bounds on bequests,
and it is timeinconsistent.
1|INTRODUCTION
Inequality across individuals is largely accounted for by the unequal distribution of wealth and
the latter is, in turn, significantly affected by intentional bequests, that is, motivated by parental
altruism. For example, Kotlikoff and Summers (1981) argue that as much as 46% of household
wealth is accounted for by bequests and Kopczuk and Lupton (2007) find that roughly 75% of
the elderly population has a bequest motive. This observation raises many normative questions.
A widely shared view is that bequests are undeserved, and the inequality they create should be
eliminated based on ethical grounds.
1
However, if bequests are the result of altruistic
preferences, a nonpaternalistic welfare criterion cannot ignore the parents' utility gains from
their children's welfare, so that wealth equalization at birth (equal opportunity) may not be
desirable from a social welfare standpoint. Then, it is natural to ask how much inequality arises
1
For instance, estate taxes and a global tax on wealth, have been famously advocated in Piketty (2014), although some authors have shown that such policies
may have unintended consequences for inequality (see Becker & Tomes, 1979).
from nonpaternalistic social welfare maximizing plans, how do these planning optima compare
with those generated in market economies, and whether they can be decentralized through
markets. In this paper I review these questions in a simple overlapping generations (olg)
economy where individuals' degrees of parental altruism is onesided and inherited, that is,
persistent across individuals belonging to the same dynasty and show that the most obvious
criteria to reduce inequality in this setting are highly problematic. To keep the model as
simple as possible, I assume that all individuals belong to two types only, with types being
defined by the degree of parental altruism. The latter is defined by a dynastyspecific inter-
generational discount rate as in Barro (1974), and it is the only source of heterogeneity between
individuals.
I consider two different approaches to social welfare. By the first approach, the planner
(or policymaker) targets some desirablelevel of consumption inequality between types in the
same generation at all time periods. More formally, one derives the Pareto Set defined as the
maximum average wellbeing of the first generations subject to the condition that all other
generations attain a minimum level of welfare (or reservation utilities). A possible interpretation
is that the planning optimum is subject to some form of limited enforcement, and that, for this
reason, the selected allocations must be sufficiently attractive to guarantee the participation
(or consensus) of all future generations (participation constraints). Allocations in the Pareto Set
can be decentralized as competitive equilibria cum lumpsum transfers and each set of
reservation utilities generates a set of individualspecific Lagrange multipliers related to the
participation constraints. Exploiting the existence of a onetoone map between reservation
utilities and allocations (and degree of inequality across types) one can interpret these multi-
pliers as individualspecific welfare weights for a time additive and separable social welfare
function. The selected allocation and consumption inequality in the Pareto Set can be inter-
preted as the solution to a standard social welfare problem where the planner's objective
corresponds to that specific social welfare function. Hence, by fixing the desired level of
consumption inequality we are effectively fixing a set of welfare weights and deriving the
planner's preferencesfor the way in which individuals' utilities should be aggregated. I show
that, whenever the planning problem generates a bounded level of inequality, these implicit
welfare weights are timedependent and nonsymmetric, in the sense that they are higher the
lower is the degree of intergenerational altruism. In fact, since the less altruistic dynasties are
characterized by a lower time discount rate (for the children's utility), any bounded value for
the target level of consumption inequality implies that the participation constraints for the
members of the less altruistic dynasty are typically binding (whereas these constraints are not
binding for the more altruistic dynasty). This biasin the values of welfare weights reflects the
need to avoid that the children of the less altruistic dynasties may reject the plan and may be
interpreted as a measure of the less altruistic dynasties' bargaining power.
The second approach to social welfare is utilitarian,thatis,derivedfromaplanningoptimum
generated by a social welfare function equal to a weighted sum of the utilities of all individuals.
Welfare weights are equal across individuals belonging to the same generation, whereas the utilities
of different generations are discounted exponentially using a social discount factor arbitrarily close
to one (to approach an equal treatment criterion). This criterion has been proposed by Bernheim
(1989)inaoneagent per generation economy (and later applied by Fahri & Werning, 2007;Phelan,
2006;Soares,2015, and others in different contexts), and I call it Utilitarian Social Welfare
2
(USW).
2
Strictly speaking, a utilitarian criterion requires identical welfare weight. The adoption of an exponential discountfactor for different generations is required to
guarantee a bounded welfare measure. As the discount factor is assumed to be arbitrarily close to one, my welfare criterion is quasi utilitarian.
1392
|
REICHLIN

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT