Selling Out: an Instrumentalist Theory of Legal Ethics

Selling Out: An Instrumentalist Theory of Legal
Ethics
KEITH N. HYLTON*
ABSTRACT
Legal ethics has received attention mostly from scholars who view it as a
f‌ield for the application of moral philosophy. However, economic analysis is
also useful in the study of legal ethics, because it can illuminate the incentives
that generate ethical dilemmas and controversies. This is especially true in the
subf‌ield this paper devotes its attention to, lawyer conf‌lict of interest rules. The
problem I focus on is the incentive of the lawyer to “sell out” his client—for
example, by providing conf‌idential information to a potential adversary or by
providing legal misinformation to the client in order to aid the adversary. The
lawyer is in a unique position to auction off the client’s legal rights to the high-
est bidder. Troublingly, in those instances where the client most values his legal
right, the lawyer will f‌ind it more prof‌itable to sell out the client than to arrange
a mutually benef‌icial consent to a conf‌lict of interest. I examine implications for
the regulation of legal ethics.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
I. CONTRIBUTION OF INCENTIVES APPROACH . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
II. LEGAL AND ECONOMIC INFRASTRUCTURE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
III. STORIES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31
IV. THE ECONOMICS OF LEGAL RIGHTS. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
A. THE VALUE OF LEGAL RIGHTS AND LEGAL
REPRESENTATION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
B. ENFORCEABLE LEGAL RIGHT. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
* William Fairf‌ield Warren Distinguished Professor, Boston University; Professor of Law, Boston
University School of Law. I thank Mike Meurer and Kathy Zeiler for helpful comments. Abena Ababio, Yoona
Cha, and Nick Sangiovanni helped with the research. © 2021, Keith N. Hylton.
19
C. LEGAL RIGHTS AND BURDENS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
D. WAIVER OF LEGAL RIGHTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
E. CONFLICT OF INTEREST . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42
F. SELLING OUT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
G. WELFARE CONSEQUENCES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
H. ILLUSTRATION 1: PATENT CIRCUMVENTION . . . . . . . . . . 47
I. ILLUSTRATION 2: TAKING PROPERTY OR STEALING A
BUSINESS, THROUGH LEGAL REPRESENTATION . . . . . . . 49
J. CONSTRAINTS ON SELLING OUT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
V. LEGAL CLAIMS. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
A. SETTLEMENT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 54
B. LITIGATION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57
VI. IMPLICATIONS FOR LAW . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61
CONCLUSION. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63
INTRODUCTION
Legal ethics has received attention mostly from scholars who view ethics as a
f‌ield for the application of moral philosophy.
1
However, economic analysis is
also useful in the study of legal ethics, because it can illuminate the incentives
that generate ethical dilemmas and controversies.
2
This is especially true in the
subf‌ield this paper devotes most of its attention to, attorney conf‌lict of interest
rules.
3
1. See, e.g., David Luban, Calming the Hearse Horse: A Philosophical Research Program for Legal Ethics,
40 MD. L. REV. 451 (1981); Thomas L. Shaffer, The Legal Ethics of Radical Individualism, 65 TEX. L. REV.
963 (1987); Alice Woolley & W. Bradley Wendel, Legal Ethics and Moral Character, 23 GEO. J. LEGAL
ETHICS 1065 (2010).
2. Although instrumentalist or incentive-based arguments are far from the dominant approach among legal
ethicists, there has been a developing undercurrent within ethics scholarship that questions the moral basis of
the traditional ethical norms, such as loyalty and the duty of conf‌identiality. See Shaffer, supra note 1, at 963;
William H. Simon, Ethical Discretion in Lawyering, 101 HARV. L. REV. 1083 (1988); Maura Strassberg,
Taking Ethics Seriously: Beyond Positivist Jurisprudence in Legal Ethics, 80 IOWA L. REV. 901 (1995).
3. See, e.g., Robert H. Aronson, Conf‌lict of Interest, 52 WASH. L. REV. 807 (1977); Nancy J. Moore,
Conf‌licts of Interest in the Simultaneous Representation of Multiple Clients: A Proposed Solution to the
Current Confusion and Controversy, 61 TEX. L. REV. 211 (1982).
20 THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS [Vol. 34:19
Economic analysis of legal ethics mostly adopts the agency cost framework,
4
which views ethical problems as emanating from the divergence of incentives
between principal and agent.
5
However, the incentives of principals and agents,
like the incentives of any two people, will always diverge to some degree.
6
Agency costs infect all relationships, and so an agency cost approach leads to the
question of which costs are signif‌icant and which ones are not.
7
Similarly, a
client-centered approach to legal ethics, which stresses the autonomy of the cli-
ent,
8
could lead one to imagine that any divergence between the incentives of
principal and agent is potentially a problem of ethics. Moreover, in the area of at-
torney conf‌licts, the divergences are really between alternative principals (one
client versus another client), not between principals and agents. For these reasons,
the agency cost framework, without some additional ref‌inement, may not be the
most promising perspective from which to analyze legal ethics.
This paper takes a different approach from agency cost theory. The approach
here is to identify the pressure points of incentive divergence, and the social costs
of failing to regulate attorney conf‌licts of interest. By starting at the ground level
with incentives, my hope is that this analysis can point to the types of interactions
where ethical constraints are most helpful, to rank ethical conf‌licts in terms of
potential for social harm and the consequent need for regulation, and to suggest
the types of regulation most likely to be benef‌icial. In evaluating the need for
4. The term “agency costs” refers to costs (or, more generally, losses in social welfare) that arise from the
divergence between the incentives of principals and agents. The term appears to have been coined by Michael
Jensen and William Meckling. See Michael C. Jensen & William H. Meckling, Theory of the Firm: Managerial
Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure, 3 J. FIN. ECON. 305, 309-10 (1976). Scholars have found
several applications of agency cost theory in the law. See, e.g., Jonathan Klick & Robert H. Sitkoff, Agency
Costs, Charitable Trusts, and Corporate Control: Evidence from Hershey’s Kiss-Off, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 749
(2008); Lee-ford Tritt, The Limitations of an Economic Agency Cost Theory of Trust Law, 32 CARDOZO L. REV.
2579 (2011).
5. Jonathan R. Macey & Geoffrey P. Miller, An Economic Analysis of Conf‌lict of Interest Regulation, 82
IOWA L. REV. 965, 968–69 (1997).
6. See Richard A. Epstein, The Legal Regulation of Lawyers’ Conf‌licts of Interest, 60 FORDHAM L. REV.
579, 581 (1992).
7. See id. at 580–81.
8. Client autonomy appears to be a basic norm underlying legal ethics. See, e.g., DAVID BINDER, PAUL B.
BERGMAN, PAUL R. TREMBLAY & IAN S. WEINSTEIN, LAWYERS AS COUNSELORS: A CLIENT-CENTERED
APPROACH (3d ed., 2011); MONROE H. FREEDMAN , LAWYERS’ ETHICS IN AN ADVERSARY SYSTEM 9 (1975);
CHARLES W. WOLFRAM, MODERN LEGAL ETHICS 146 (1986); Charles Fried, The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral
Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation, 85 YALE L. J. 1060, 1061 (1976); Stephen L. Pepper, Autonomy,
Community, and Lawyers’ Ethics, 19 CAP. U. L. REV. 939, 939–40 (1990); Stephen L. Pepper, The Lawyer’s
Amoral Ethical Role: A Defense, A Problem, and Some Possibilities, AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 613, 614 (1986);
Fred C. Zacharias, Limits on Client Autonomy in Legal Ethics Regulation, 81 B.U. L. REV. 199, 199–200
(2001). For a modern equivocal defense of the autonomy norm and lawyering, see DANIEL MARKOVITS , A
MODERN LEGAL ETHICS: ADVERSARY ADVOCACY IN A DEMOCRATIC AGE 3 (2008). Of course, limited informa-
tion on the part of the client may justify paternalism in the legal profession, which clashes with the autonomy
norm, but even the paternalism defense takes autonomy as the appropriate default norm. See David Luban,
Paternalism and the Legal Profession, 1981 WIS. L. REV. 454, 464–65 (1981). Some authors have rejected the
autonomy norm. See, e.g., Shaffer, supra note 1, at 969–70; Simon, supra note 2, at 1116–18.
2021] SELLING OUT 21

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT