Self-Ownership and Self-Alienation: Three Case Studies

Date03 August 2011
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1108/S1059-4337(2011)0000056004
Published date03 August 2011
Pages1-36
AuthorEthan MacAdam
SELF-OWNERSHIP AND
SELF-ALIENATION: THREE
CASE STUDIES
Ethan MacAdam
ABSTRACT
This chapter addresses the alienability or inalienability of the bodily self
by looking at continuing legal, economic, and cultural issues surrounding
three case studies: the growth of cell lines, live organ transfer, and the
practices of ‘‘forced prostitution’’ as a contemporary form of slavery.
The essay contends that it is, ironically, Locke and Hegel’s shared
hyperliberal notion of the self as inalienable property that sustains a
potential basis, in law and in culture, for troubling cases of self-alienation
which persist in the case studies offered.
While the state of knowledge across both the human and the natural
sciences has done a great deal to disassemble the entrenched western
doctrines of mind/body dualism, we still regularly resort, in law as in other
endeavors, to the integrity of both entities: of a consciousness which is also
the locus of intellectual/creative activity and psychological character on the
one hand, and a physiologically discrete organism as the seat and instrument
of that consciousness on the other. Yet, again, we no longer live (if we ever
did) in a world where such dualism withstands scrutiny: as earnestly as
Special Issue: Human Rights: New Possibilities/New Problems
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society, Volume 56, 1–36
Copyright r2011 by Emerald Group Publishing Limited
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1108/S1059-4337(2011)0000056004
1
Deleuze and Guattari (1977) asserted the psychological self to be far more
diffuse than the physiological body of everyday life (which that self imagines
in turn as similarly diffuse), so daily life reiterates to us that the body has far
less integrity than a nominally unified psychological self may often need to
suppose. Controversy over the collection of individuals’ DNA from remnant
biological materials, for example, reminds us that we daily slough off minute
amounts of our physical selves; and even if we regard our alienation of
bodily wastes as the return of ingested materials to the environment, there is,
as at least one scholar has previously noted, a more genuine self-partition
involved in men’s alienation of reproductive material in sexual activity, or of
a woman’s giving birth to a child. More mundanely, we cut our hair and
nails; we lose bodily matter when we are wounded; on occasion, we donate
blood and even organs, and we may cause tissue to be excised in surgical
procedures.
The converse of this phenomenon – that we daily incorporate outside
matter into our bodies, most often via ingestion – is somehow more familiar
to us, as is the varied integration of our environment and of beings around
us into our physical and mental functioning. Partition of or subtraction from
the self, however – the alienation of our body or any part of it – usually rubs
against our intuitions as unnatural and as deeply illiberal. Discomfited as we
may be, for instance, with the pace of biotechnology that increasingly
promises to add (even on a nominally voluntary basis) organic and
inorganic components to our bodies in ways that may also offend our ideals
of the bodily self’s autonomy, our prohibitions against alienation of or from
that self are far older and stronger; not only shall no individual be deprived
of his or her physical liberty without just cause, but none shall similarly
overcome that same individual’s will and intentions for their own body, nor
have a power of disposal over any part of that body.
So strident is this prohibition that liberalism finds its limits here as well: in
most contemporary law codes, no person can willfully alienate their body or
control of it to another in such a way as might be enforced by physical
coercion, and no contractual agreement can create such an arrangement.
This point is important: physical alienation of the body (by others and/or by
the self) is forbidden at the physical level. Many other courses, after all,
remain open to one who seeks to induce bodily acts in another, even to have
disposal over another’s body or its parts (via regimes of psychology,
economy, etc.), and we may also conceive of an individual who succeeds
in voluntarily ‘‘enslaving’’ himself to another’s will by substituting his
own self-discipline for the threat of violence (i.e., as outlined by Foucault,
1995, pp. 195–228), but these would not be cases of self-alienation in the
ETHAN MACADAM2
physical-material sense so offensive to us (though they might certainly prove
offensive in other jurisprudence). Self-alienation, marked by the surrender
of some or all of the body, matters most as a physical fact.
This essay, then, examines the case for asserting, descriptively and/or
normatively, the inalienability of the bodily self;
1
because the alienation thus
denied does matter most in physical contexts, however, I want to frame this
argument in terms of the question of the self as an inalienable property,
rather than as the object of inalienable rights of ownership. This is an
awkward distinction because property/ownership in the western legal
tradition is of course a name for a constellation of rights (disposition, use
extending to consumption, retention, abandonment, etc.),
2
and so we might
readily say that we are always speaking of the latter in speaking of the
former. I make no objection to this idea, but it remains that these rights
always have an object,asomething, in some aspect material and tangible,
3
to
which they apply, and that we do not conceive of property without
consciousness of both the abstract rights and this material substrate (‘‘So
inexorable is the movement from property to things (so inescapable the
probability that property will be a thing),’’ says Best, 2004, p. 52, n. 43).
When I speak (or wish to speak) in this essay about inalienable property,
then, the issue becomes confused – as J. S. Mill pointed out, the idea of
private property at least potentially presupposes alienability (see Radin,
1987, pp. 1888–1889), and to posit a kind of property which cannot be
alienated seems in some sense to disqualify the material in question as
property – something that cannot be alienated cannot be owned. But the
discourse of our jurisprudence does not proceed along this path – instead,
we usually cannot help but conceive of ‘‘inalienable’’ material as property
owned by (or as) the individual from whom it cannot be alienated.
By contrast, inalienability is not a problem for our discourse of rights,
which we do not regard ourselves as ‘‘owning’’ in this way; we ‘‘possess’’
rights certainly, but the semantic difference highlights the fact that rights are
of course intangible and abstract in a way that the material substrates they
may apply to never are. Some rights (like at least some property) are
alienable (‘‘waivable’’ in the language of rights) in themselves in a formal
sense (e.g., the Fifth Amendment’s right against self-incrimination); as for
rights we may call inalienable (and it is to these that notions of inalienable
property are usually linked), highly complex and in some cases metaphysical
questions attend the idea of what would constitute alienation of such rights
(if we do not exercise a right, do we still possess it in that declination? and if
we are prevented from exercising it? by physical force, by other means?).
This is true precisely because rights are largely intangible abstracts: we are
Self-Ownership and Self-Alienation: Three Case Studies 3

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT