Scrutinizing Sex Under Natural law: Unitive Sex, Self-Gratifying Sex, and Concepts of Harm

AuthorMarvin Lim
PositionYale Law School, J.D.; Emory University, B.A. For editorial guidance, my substantial thanks to Zachary O'Driscoll, Carley Kranstuber, and the staff of the Capital University Law Review. A special note of gratitude to the late Robert 'Bo' Burt, for inspiring this piece and reading earlier drafts.
Pages579-634
SCRUTINIZING SEX UNDER NATURAL LAW: UNITIVE
SEX, SELF-GRATIFYING SEX, AND CONCEPTS OF HARM
MARVIN LIM*
I. INTRODUCTION
Governmental regulation of sexuality is undergoing tremendous
changes, particularly as the question of same-sex marriage has reached the
Supreme Court of the United States.1 As this question suggests, it is not
just what is and is not appropriate for the government to regulate at stake,
but also the underlying question of the morality of sex. The conflict over
sexual morality often plays out in one side arguing for individual rights and
the other side arguing that every act of sex must take into account larger
societal consequences.2 Those who argue in favor of sex positivity—the
idea that sexual pleasure in and of itself is a positive good that should be
valued and not stigmatized—tend to stress that a person should have the
freedom to control his or her own body.3 This conceptualization of sexual
morality places a high value on the concepts of bodily autonomy and
personal privacy.4 Those who favor a more traditional conceptualization
of sexual morality stress the broader consequences of sex beyond the
individual, such as pregnancy and parenthood, the formation of families
Copyright © 2017, Marvin Lim.
* Yale Law School, J.D.; Emory University, B.A. For editorial guidance, my
substantial thanks to Zachary O’Driscoll, Carley Kranstuber, and the staff of the Capital
University Law Review. A special note of gratitude to the late Robert “Bo” Burt, for
inspiring this piece and reading earlier dr afts.
1 Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S. Ct. 2584, 260405 (2015) (holding that the Fourteenth
Amendment recognizes a right to two people of the same sex to obtain a state marriage
license).
2 One of the most famous iterations of this debate is that between H.L.A. Hart and John
Devlin. Cf. H.L.A. HART, LAW, LIBERTY, AND MORALITY 4–6 (1963) (advocating against
regulation of moral offenses); PATRICK DEVLIN, THE ENFORCEMENT OF MORALS 5–7 (1968)
(arguing that moral offenses can be regulated) .
3 See, e.g., Gayle Rubin, Thinking Sex: Notes for a Radical Theory of the Politics of
Sexuality, in PLEASURE AND DANGER 267, 283 (1984) (“A democratic morality should judge
sexual acts by the way partners treat one another, the level of mutual consideration, the
presence or absence of coercion, and th e quantity and quality of the pleasures they
provide.”).
4 See id.
580 CAPITAL UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [45:579
and lineage, and the sustenance of the human population.5 They argue that
every sexual act morally implicates and has consequences for these ideas,
including, by necessity, those that consciously attempt to avoid
parenthood.6
Among the loudest, and perhaps most interesting voice on these
questions is that of the Catholic Church, particularly to the extent that the
Catholic Church posits not just religious doctrine, but also a more
secularized “natural law” to support its position on both the morality and
the regulation of sex alike.7 What is particularly interesting is the Catholic
Church’s conceptualization of how human beings dignify—and are
dignified by—one another in sex.
This issue on which that Catholic doctrine is particularly focused
highlights consequences of sex, less far-reaching than parenthood and
family, yet broader than one individual and her autonomy: sex speaks to
the question of what kind of regard we owe to another human being in our
immediate interpersonal interactions with them.8 Of course, it is hardly
only Catholic doctrine that recognizes this. Sex positive scholar Gayle
Rubin herself puts it rather astutely: while rejecting an analysis of sex in
terms of “sin, disease, neurosis, pathology, decadence, pollution, or the
decline and fall of empires,” she urges us to think of sex in the less morally
loaded terms of “populations, neighborhoods, settlement patterns,
migration, urban conflict, epidemiology, and police technology.”9 As she
states, “[s]exuality is as much a human product as are diets, methods of
transportation, systems of etiquette, forms of labor, types of entertainment,
processes of production, and modes of oppression. Once sex is understood
5 See, e.g., SHERI F GIRGIS, RYAN T. ANDERSON, & ROBERT P. GEORGE, WHAT IS
MARRIAGE? MAN AND WOM AN: A DEFENSE 74 (2012) (“To form a true marriage, a couple
needs to establish the comprehensive mind-and-body union that would be completed by and
apt for procreation and domestic life and that thus inherently calls for permanent and
exclusive commitment.”).
6 See id.
7 See, e.g., Sherif Girgis, The Historic Christian Teaching Against Contraception: A
Defense, PUB. DISCOURSE (Aug. 10, 2016), http://www.thepublicdiscourse.com/
2016/08/17559 [https://perma.cc/E2HD-2GXJ] (“A contraceptive culture therefore tends to
privatize adult desire and prioritize it over ch ildren’s needs.”).
8 See Pope John Paul II, Lust Limits Nuptial Meaning of the Body, ETERN AL WORD
TELEVISION NETWORK (June 30, 1980), https://www.ewtn.com/library/PAPALDOC/
jp2tb30.htm [https://perma.cc/WRU2-PM63].
9 See Rubin, supra note 3, at 277.
2017] SCRUTINIZING SEX 581
in terms of social analysis and historical understanding, a more realistic
politics of sex becomes possible.”10 In highlighting these factors that
influence sexual tastesand particularly in pointing out that sex “is as
much a human product as are diets”—Rubin illuminates the idea that our
tastes must always impute our desire, and just as importantly our disgust,
towards other human beings.11 Where sexual conduct involves more than
just one person, our desires and disgusts are actualized through another
human being.12 In this way, what kind of regard we owe to another human
being is a question that is inevitably present during sex—a question that
Catholic sexual morality in particular seeks to answer.13
It is this question that this Article explores, particularly from the
lens—and through simultaneous critique—of Catholic sexual morality and
the body of so-called natural law it has inspired. More specifically, this
Article looks at the idea, which is an integral part of Catholic morality and
natural law on sexuality, that sex must be motivated not by lustwhich is
considered both subrational and insufficiently respectful of other human
beings—but by greater reason and purpose that gives due regard to
others.14 In sex that is morally licit, a person “is not just a passive object,
defined by his or her own body and sex . . . .”15 Instead, a person must be
“‘given’ to the other as a unique and unrepeatable subject, as ‘self,’ as a
person.”16 As this Article will establish, Catholic morality and natural law
establish that, for this to be possible, sex must be “unitive,” involving a
married man and woman who seek to fulfill the positive good of
marriage—a conceptualization that, most visibly, is key to natural law and
Catholic morality’s condemnation of same-sex sexual conduct.17
By contrast, in sex that is illicit, “lust of the flesh directs these [sexual]
desires . . . to satisfaction of the body, often at the cost of a real and full
10 Id.
11 Id. at 277.
12 Id. at 279.
13 Id. at 278.
14 Id.
15 Pope John Paul II, Analysis of Knowledge and of Procreation, ETERNAL WORD
TELEVISION NETWORK (Mar. 10, 1980) [hereinafter Knowledge and Procreation],
http://www.ewtn.com/library/papaldoc/jp2tb19.htm [https://perma.cc/TY2U-SVZE].
16 Id.
17 Pope Paul VI, Encyclical Letter: Humanae Vitae, HOLY SEE (July 25, 1968),
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/paul_vi/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-vi_enc_25071968_
humanae-vitae_en.html [https://perma.cc/5WAZ-R6LA].

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT