Science and Pseudoscience in Law Enforcement

Date01 October 2008
DOI10.1177/0093854808321526
Published date01 October 2008
Subject MatterArticles
SCIENCE AND PSEUDOSCIENCE IN LAW
ENFORCEMENT
A User-Friendly Primer
SCOTT O. LILIENFELD
KRISTIN LANDFIELD
Emory University, Atlanta, Georgia
Pseudoscience and questionable science are largely neglected problems in police and other law enforcement work. In this
primer, the authors delineate the key differences between science and pseudoscience, presenting 10 probabilistic indicators
or warning signs, such as lack of falsifiability, absence of safeguards against confirmation bias, and lack of self-correction,
that can help consumers of the police literature to distinguish scientific from pseudoscientific claims. Each of these warning
signs is illustrated with an example from law enforcement. By attending to the differences between scientific and
pseudoscientific assertions, police officers and other law enforcement officials can minimize their risk of errors and make
better real-world decisions.
Keywords: pseudoscience; police; law enforcement; falsifiability; peer review; confirmation bias
Throughout their careers, police and other law enforcement officials face an enormous
array of challenges involving threats to life and liberty: questions of innocence versus
guilt, split-second decisions regarding how to respond in a crisis, attempts to locate miss-
ing persons and solve serious crimes, lie detection, and the reconstruction of past criminal
events, to name but a few. The accuracy of these techniques has the potential to determine
crucial decisions, even those involving life or death. As in most professions, individuals in
law enforcement must evaluate techniques with a critical eye before using them. Like all
disciplines that interpret data to make real-world decisions, police work can easily fall prey
to the seductive charms of pseudoscience.
Given these formidable challenges, it is hardly surprising that law enforcement officials
have turned to scientific psychology for assistance in developing valid forensic techniques
and evaluating the validity of scores of others. In the 1870s, Sir Francis Galton, cousin of
Charles Darwin, experimented with a word association test (in which a test examiner says
a word, like “money,” and awaits a response from the respondent) as a tool for lie detection
(Matte, 2002). Similarly, in the early 1900s, Hugo Munsterberg (1908) performed classic
demonstrations that underscored the fallibility of eyewitness testimony. Since then, psycho-
logical researchers have spearheaded the development of scientifically grounded proce-
dures to enhance the accuracy of forensic techniques.
1215
CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND BEHAVIOR, Vol. 35 No. 10,October 2008 1215-1230
DOI: 10.1177/0093854808321526
© 2008 International Association for Correctional and Forensic Psychology
AUTHORS’ NOTE: The authors thank Dr. Carol Tavris, Dr. Brent Snook, and an anonymous reviewer for
their extremely helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article. All correspondence concerning this article
should be addressed to Scott O. Lilienfeld, PhD, Department of Psychology, Room 206, Emory University, 532
Kilgo Circle, Atlanta, Georgia 30322; e-mail: slilien@emory.edu.
Nevertheless, like many professions, including psychology itself, law enforcement has
long struggled with the thorny problem of distinguishing scientifically supported from sci-
entifically unsupported practices. Because much of police work has developed in isolation
from psychological science, its practices are a jumbled mix of legitimate and illegitimate
claims (see Brewer & Wilson, 1995, for an introduction). This special issue of Criminal
Justice and Behavior focuses on the largely neglected problem of pseudoscience in police
work and highlights several prominent examples of law enforcement techniques that fall
either on or outside the murky fringes of pseudoscience.
PSEUDOSCIENCE DEFINED
Before discussing specific law enforcement techniques that fall under the broad umbrella
of pseudoscience, we must define pseudoscience and how it differs from bona fide science.
Traditionally, pseudosciences are disciplines that possess the superficial appearance of
science but lack its substance (Lilienfeld, 1999; Ruscio, 2006). More informally, pseudo-
sciences are imposters of science: They do not play by the rules of science even though they
mimic some of its outward features. As a consequence, they can easily mislead untrained
observers into concluding that they possess scientific merit. A cousin of pseudoscience is
“junk science,” sometimes described as the intrusion of scientifically unwarranted claims
into the courtroom (Huber, 1991; Park, 2001).
Pseudosciences have a hoary and checkered history in psychology (Leahey & Leahey,
1983). Such disciplines as phrenology, physiognomy, parapsychology (the study of
extrasensory perception and psychokinesis), astrology, and subliminal persuasion for
advertising purposes, among many others (see Hines, 2003), have traditionally displayed
many of the telltale signs of pseudoscience. Nevertheless, pseudosciences are defined not
by their object of study per se but by their approach to evidence, especially negative evi-
dence (Lilienfeld, Lynn, & Lohr, 2003). In contrast to most developed sciences, which
eventually—if often reluctantly—assimilate negative evidence into their corpus of belief,
most pseudosciences remain largely insulated from contradictory data. It is in principle
possible to approach parapsychology, for example, from a scientific perspective, assuming
that investigators are willing to admit well-replicated negative data into their web of belief
and revise their hypotheses accordingly. Nevertheless, many parapsychologists (e.g.,
Radin, 1997) have not done so and insist that the evidence for extrasensory perception and
related phenomena is promising or even conclusive despite approximately 150 years of
repeated failures to replicate initial positive findings (Gilovich, 1991; Hyman, 1989).
Philosopher of science Mario Bunge (1983) proposed the categories of “research fields”
and “belief fields” to demarcate sciences from pseudosciences, arguing that scientific prac-
tices are distinguished by research support as opposed to intuition or faith. For instance,
subjective experience and intuition alone are insufficient for police officers to believe that
their interrogation procedures produce accurate confessions; these procedures must be
validated by scientific evidence.
Science and pseudoscience are not always easy to distinguish, because they probably fall
at opposite ends of a continuum, differing in degree rather than in kind (Lilienfeld, 1999;
Lilienfeld et al., 2003). Like many mental concepts, pseudoscience is probably an open
concept (see Meehl, 1986) or “Roschian concept” (see Rosch, 1973; Rosch & Mervis,
1216 CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND BEHAVIOR

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT