Religious Pluralism, Equal Opportunity, and the State

Published date01 March 1991
Date01 March 1991
DOI10.1177/106591299104400111
Subject MatterArticles
RELIGIOUS
PLURALISM,
EQUAL
OPPORTUNITY,
AND
THE
STATE
GLORIA
T.
BECKLEY
AND
PAUL
BURSTEIN
University
of
Washington
mericans
have
historically
enjoyed
considerable
freedom
of reli-
~~
gious
belief
(or
nonbelief)
and
worship.
Yet
their
freedom
to
A
pursue
their
religious
tenets
has
been
constrained
in
at
least
two
ways.
First,
Americans
have
often
been
hostile
to
religious
minor-
ities.
Adherents
of
minority
religions
often
felt
that
if
they
wanted
to
gain
access
to
educational
opportunities
or
desirable
jobs
or
housing,
they
should
hide
(or
change)
their
beliefs
and
denominational
member-
ships,
and
minimize
the
expression
of
distinctive
religious
practices.
Second,
American
law
has
long
distinguished
between
religious
belief
and
religious
practice.
&dquo;When ...
one’s
religious
beliefs
encom-
passed
consequences
for
one’s
daily
secular
life,
then
freedom
of
reli-
gious
often
has
been
problematic,&dquo;
note
Way
and
Burt
(1983:
652);
&dquo; ...
the
freedom
to
act
on
the
basis
of
one’s
religious
beliefs
may
be
narrowly
circumscribed
by
public
opinion
and
the
law.&dquo;
However,
changes
in
American
society
during
the
last
several
decades
may
have
significantly
reduced
both
the
legal
and
socio-
economic
constraints
experienced
by
religious
minorities.
Not
only
has
prejudice
against
religious
minorities
declined,
but
legal
doctrine
has
been
altered
as
well.
Way
and
Burt
argue
that
changes
in
judi-
cial
interpretations
of
the
free
exercise
clause
beginning
in
the
1960s
produced
a
&dquo;more
generous
and
accepting
spirit&dquo;
toward
the
RECEIVED:
November
1,
1989
FIRST
REVISION
RECEIVED:
April
2,
1990
SECOND
REVISION
RECEIVED:
June
13,
1990
ACCEPTED
FOR
PUBLICATION:
June
15,
1990
NOTE:
Revision
of
a
paper
presented
to
the
annual
meeting
of
the
American
Sociological
Association,
San
Francisco,
California,
August
13,
1989.
The
work
was
made
possible
by
grants
from
the
American
Jewish
Committee
and
the
National
Science
Foundation
(SES-8509055),
and
is
based
in
part
on
a
report
to
the
Committee.
For
helpful
advice
and
comments
we
would
like
to
thank
David
Singer,
Lawrence
Grossman,
Calvin
Goldscheider,
Sam
Rabinove,
Alfred
Blumrosen,
Arval
Morris,
Cornelius
Peck,
Marvin
Stern,
Florence
Katz,
Lisa
Cubbins,
Marshall
George,
Terence
C.
Halliday,
Judy
Howard,
Satoshi
Kanazawa,
Satomi
Kurosu,
Ken
Pike,
Xinhua
Ren,
Stuart
Scheingold,
Gi-Wook
Shin,
Edie
Simpson,
Beth
Weinstein,
and
Siok-Cheng
Yeoh.
186
religious
practices
of
marginal
religions.
&dquo;If
the
Bill
of
Rights
is
intended
to
protect
minorities,&dquo;
they
write
(1983:
665),
&dquo;then
at
long
last
mar-
ginal
or
dissident
religions
have
found
a
measure
of
constitutional
protection.&dquo;
Furthermore,
in
a
dramatic
break
with
the
past,
government
has
gone
beyond
simply
allowing
free
exercise
(up
to
a
point)
to
actively
intervening
in
social
and
economic
life
to
ensure
that
Americans
are
not
deprived
of
access
to
jobs,
public
accommodations,
education,
or
housing
because
of
the
religious
prejudices
of
their
fellow
citizens.
The
Civil
Rights
Act
of
1964
and
other
major
civil
rights
laws
pro-
hibit
discrimination
on
the
basis
of
religion
as
well
as
race,
national
origin,
and,
in
some
areas,
sex.
Passage
of
the
civil
rights
laws
meant,
according
to
the
historian
J.
R.
Pole
(1978:
326),
that
&dquo;[flor
the
first
time
in
American
history,
equality
became
a
major
object
of
govern-
ment
policy.&dquo;
But
what
is
the
nature
of
the
equality
mandated
by
the
civil
rights
laws?
Do
such
laws
require-in
line
with
the
earlier,
more
restrictive
readings
of the
free
exercise
clause - only
that
individuals
not
be
penalized
for
religious
affiliation
and
belief?
Or
might
the
concept
of
equality
be
expanded - as
interpretations
of
the
free
exercise
clause
have
broadened - to
include
the
notion
that
society
should
accommo-
date,
to
some
degree,
the
religious
practices
of
adherents
to
minority
religions?
As
the
scope
of
federal
government
activity
has
extended
to
the
regulation
of
employment
practices,
it
has
had
to
address
this
issue
and
to
confront
two
competing
views
of
what
constitutes
fair
treatment
for
religious
minorities
in
the
labor
market.
One - the
&dquo;assimilationist&dquo;
view
(Post
1988:
103) - argues
that
nondiscrimination
means
forbid-
ding
employers
to
distinguish
among
employees
on
the
basis
of
reli-
gious
affiliation
or
belief.
If
employees’
religious
practices
interfere
with
standard
business
practices,
however-if,
for
example,
some
employ-
ees
want
special
days
off
for
religious
reasons -
the
employer
has
no
obligation
to
accommodate
them,
and
the
government
has
no
reason
to
prevent
the
employees
from
being
penalized.
The
competing-or
&dquo;cultural
pluralist&dquo;
(Post
1988:
106)-view
claims
that
it
is
important
to
accommodate
religious
practices
as
well
as
beliefs.
Full
acceptance
of
religious
minorities
would
mean
going
beyond
treating
members
of
all
religions
identically;
true
nondiscrimination
means
granting
legitimacy
to
minority
religious
practices
as
well
as
beliefs
(see
also
Galanter
1966).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT