Religiosity as a Determinant of Happiness

AuthorErich Gundlach,Matthias Opfinger
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/rode.12047
Published date01 August 2013
Date01 August 2013
Religiosity as a Determinant of Happiness
Erich Gundlach and Matthias Opfinger*
Abstract
The empirical relation between happiness and religiosity is considered from the perspective of basic utility
theory. An unbalanced cross-country panel data set is used to study whether religiosity can be considered
as a substitute in the happiness function, which itself is held to be a proxy for the utility function. We find
that the same level of happiness can be maintained with high and low levels of religiosity as a result of sub-
stitution along a standard indifference curve. Our empirical results are consistent with three stylized facts of
the empirical literature, namely a positive correlation between happiness and religiosity, a positive correla-
tion between happiness and income, and a negative correlation between religiosity and income.
1. Religiosity, Happiness, and Utility Theory
Religious behavior does not generate a direct financial reward to believers, but it
cannot be questioned that religious activities generate subjective happiness. Hence
religiosity appears to be a plausible determinant of happiness. Since happiness is
often considered to be a plausible proxy for utility it is almost self-evident to address
any presumed link between religiosity and happiness from the perspective of basic
utility theory. However, the theoretical link between happiness and religiosity has not
been established in the literature. The present study aims to fill this gap. We develop
a simple theoretical framework to be used as a point of reference when assessing the
empirical evidence on various links between religiosity and happiness.
The Easterlin paradox has long been held to be at odds with the idea that happiness
is a proxy for utility. Easterlin (1973, 1974, 1995) states that rich people generally
report higher levels of happiness than poor people, but rising average incomes do not
increase happiness beyond a satiation point. Accordingly, an increase in income
beyond the satiation point only seems to shift the reference point within a society,
without affecting utility as proxied by a measure of happiness. This conclusion contra-
dicts textbook utility theory, where changes in income always shift the indifference
curve to a higher level of utility.
This puzzle evoked two theoretical reactions in research on happiness. Frey and
Stutzer (2006) appeal to mistakes in rational decision making in cases where reported
levels of happiness do not correspond with utility maximization. Accepting a better
paid job with higher commuting cost should not result in less happiness, but there
appears to be evidence that it does. Criticizing the assumption that individuals sys-
tematically fail to maximize their utility, Becker and Rayo (2008) argue that measures
* Gundlach: GIGA (German Institute of Global and Area Studies) and University of Hamburg, 20148
Hamburg, Germany. Tel: +49-40-42887438; Fax: +49-40-4107945; E-mail: gundlach@giga-hamburg.de.
Opfinger: Department of Economics, Trier University, 54286 Trier, Germany. For comments and sugges-
tions on earlier versions we are grateful to seminar participants at the ISNE 2010 Conference in Dublin, the
SSE Annual Meeting 2011 in Houston, the Market and Happiness Conference 2011 in Milan, and the
Annual Meeting of the Research Committee on Development Economics 2011 in Berlin, and to Michael
Funke, Olaf Hübler, Bernd Lucke, Martin Paldam, Ulrich Schmidt, Holger Strulik, and an anonymous
referee.
Review of Development Economics, 17(3), 523–539, 2013
DOI:10.1111/rode.12047
© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
of happiness and the reported Easterlin paradox might not be founded on utility
theory at all. They consider subjective happiness as an argument of the utility function
rather than a direct proxy for utility itself. According to their approach, utility would
remain in the realm of the empirically unknown and a decline of happiness with rising
income could be interpreted as a simple substitution effect.
It is not without irony that the rationalization of the Easterlin paradox by Becker
and Rayo (2008) has been published as a comment to an empirical study by Stevenson
and Wolfers (2008) that rejects the Easterlin paradox. Deaton (2008) and Sacks et al.
(2010) also provide strong evidence for a robust positive link between aggregate indi-
cators of happiness and (log) per capita income across countries and over time. More-
over, the estimated effects of income on happiness closely resemble the well-known
within-country correlation between individual levels of happiness and individual
income.
The new empirical evidence allows for a fresh start of empirical research on happi-
ness and religiosity that is based on a standard model of utility maximization. We
revise the model proposed by Becker and Rayo (2008) by treating happiness as a
direct proxy for utility, which has also been the starting point of the older empirical
happiness literature (Frey and Stutzer 2002). Accordingly, higher income should be
reflected by higher-level indifference curves for happiness. Religiosity enters as one of
the commodities of the happiness function. We show that our theoretical framework
can account for three stylized facts of the empirical literature, namely a positive corre-
lation between happiness and income, a positive correlation between happiness and
religiosity, and a negative correlation between religiosity and income.
2. Basic Results of the Empirical Literature on Happiness and Religiosity
Ellison (1991) divides religious involvement into denominational ties, divine relations,
existential certainty, and social integration. Religious involvement is reported to be
positively correlated with subjective well-being. Similarly, Greene and Yoon (2004)
assert that subjective well-being rises with religious attachment measured by the will-
ingness to attend religious services regularly. Ferriss (2002) confirms a positive corre-
lation between happiness and the frequency of church attendance but points to
denominational and doctrinal differences across churches.
One strand of the literature discusses the effects of religious activities on well-being
over the life cycle. Peacock and Poloma (1999) define religiosity by the four catego-
ries personal devotion, participation in public ritual, divine interaction, and the pref-
erence for public or private religiosity. They suggest that religiosity increases with age
and as such tends to increase reported well-being. Ardelt (2003) uses a survey method
to analyze the relationship between well-being of elderly people and different indica-
tors for intrinsic and extrinsic religious orientation. She shows that religious affiliation
and the frequency of religious attendance reduce the fear and increase the acceptance
of death, but a purpose in life is found to be more important for the well-being of
elderly people than holding religious beliefs per se.1
Lelkes (2006) uses the economic transition in Hungary after the collapse of
socialism as an exogenous shock and corroborates that higher church attendance is
positively correlated with reported well-being. Hayo (2007) also investigates the
determinants of happiness across Eastern Europe after the collapse of the socialist
systems and finds that frequent churchgoers report a significantly higher life satisfac-
tion than those who do not attend church, with no difference in life satisfaction across
different denominations. Elliott and Hayward (2009) use responses from the World
524 Erich Gundlach and Matthias Opfinger
© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT