On the Relation Between Chapters One and Two of John Stuart Mill's On Liberty

AuthorFrederick Schauer
Pages571-592
ON THE RELATION BETWEEN CHAPTERS ONE AND
TWO OF JOHN STUART MILL’S ON LIBERTY
FREDERICK SCHAUER*
John Stuart Mill‘s essay On Liberty is an icon of the liberal tradition.1
It is without question the most important articulation of the classical liberal
(or, if you will, libertarian) position that the state has no legitimate
authority to restrict the actions of an individual except when those actions
produce harm to others. And On Liberty is also among the preeminent
defenses of a distinct principle of freedom of speech, or, as Mill expressed
it, a liberty of thought and discussion.2
Mill‘s defense of the so-called Harm Principle is the chief concern of
Chapter One of On Liberty, where Mill sets out and explains his ―one very
simple principle‖:3
[T]he sole end for which mankind are warranted,
individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty
of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That
the only purpose for which power can be rightfully
exercised over any member of a civilized community,
against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own
good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant.4
Chapter Two of On Liberty, entitled ―On the Liberty of Thought and
Discussion,‖ appears initially to address a different topic. That is, although
a liberty of thought might well be understood to be an instance of the self-
regarding conduct that is the subject of Chapter One,5 ―discussion‖ seems
different. Discussion, which in its standard sense for non-delusional
Copyright © 2011, Frederick Schauer.
* David and Mary Harrison Distinguished Professor of Law, University of Virginia.
This essay was initially presented as a comment on Professor Vincent Blasis John E.
Sullivan Lecture at the Capital University Law School on April 8, 2010. I am grateful to
the students and faculty at Capital for their hospitality and to Vince Blasi for many years of
stimulating conversation about freedom of speech and much else.
1 See JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY (David Bromwich & George Kateb eds., Yale
Univ. Press 2003) (1859).
2 See id. at 86120.
3 Id. at 80.
4 Id.
5 On Mills distinction between self-regarding and other-regarding conduct, see R.J.
Halliday, Some Recent Interpretatio ns of John Stuart Mill, 43 PHIL. 1 (1968).
572 CAPITAL UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [39:571
people typically requires multiple participants, is almost by definition the
kind of other-regarding conduct that affects others. Moreover, although
most communications, just like most actions, are harmless, the capacity of
discussion, expression, speech, printing, and other forms of public
communication to cause harm in the ordinary sense of ―harm‖ appears
plain.6 Damage to reputation, mental anguish, exposure of embarrassing
facts, and persuasion to commit antisocial acts, among many others, are the
kinds of harmful consequences sometimes produced by the communicative
acts of others.7 Thus, it seems simply mistaken to treat communication as
a category of harmless actions, or even, albeit more controversially, as a
type whose tokens are statistically less likely to be harmful than the tokens
of the type we call actions.8 Consequently, there appears initially to be
some tension between Chapters One and Two of On Liberty. More
specifically, it is by no means clear whether Chapter Two and the liberty of
thought and discussion were intended by Mill (or are best understood) to
represent an example of the kind of self-regarding conduct he discussed in
Chapter One, or if instead Mill believed that the liberty of, especially,
discussion was, in effect, an exception to the principles set forth in Chapter
One, to be protected not because of its harmlessness, but, and for other
reasons, despite the harm it could cause.
In his Sullivan Lecture, Professor Blasi offers an insightful and
imaginative interpretation of Mill‘s views on harm and the consequences
of thought and discussion that render Mill‘s arguments in Chapters One
6 My own views on the harm-producing capacities of communication, and the
implications of that fact for free speech theory, are set out in, inter alia, FREDERICK
SCHAUER, FREE SPEECH: A PHILOSOPHICAL ENQUIR Y 1012 (1982) [ hereinafter SCHAUER,
FREE SPEECH]; Frederick S chauer, Is It Better to Be Safe tha n Sorry?: F ree Speech and the
Preca utionary Pr inciple, 36 PEPP. L. REV. 30 1 (2009); Frederick Schauer, The
Phenomenology of Speech a nd Ha rm, 103 ETHICS 635 (1993) [hereinafter Schauer, The
Phenomenology]; Frederick Schauer, Uncoupling Fr ee Speech, 92 COLUM. L. REV. 1321
(1992).
7 See SCHAUER, FREE SPEECH, supra note 6, at 10.
8 An assumption to just this effect—―[i]t is almost certainly true [that] in the
overwhelming majority of cases that speech is less immediately dangerous than conduct‖—
can be found in MARTIN H. REDISH, FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS 1 9
n.48 (1984). Once we recognize that almost all conduct is not dangerous, whether
immediately or otherwise, however, the factual basis for Redishs conclusion appears
elusive.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT