Rejecting the culture of independence: Corporate lawyers as committed to their clients

Published date24 September 2010
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1108/S1059-4337(2010)0000052005
Date24 September 2010
Pages33-71
AuthorRobert Eli Rosen
REJECTING THE CULTURE OF
INDEPENDENCE: CORPORATE
LAWYERS AS COMMITTED TO
THEIR CLIENTS
Robert Eli Rosen
ABSTRACT
This chapter proposes that corporate lawyers be studied as committed
to their clients, asking how they advance exercises of power by those
whom they have chosen to represent. Currently, corporate lawyers are
studied as independent from their clients, asking how they resist client
demands. Such research continues despite repeated findings that
corporate lawyers are not independent. This chapter explains the puzzling
persistence of independence by cultural understandings of both profes-
sionalism and law. It recovers a submerged historic voice in which
corporate lawyers are judged by their position in a network of relations. It
argues that it was the organization of the corporate law firm as a factory
which allowed it to become a professional ideal. Market competition has
led corporate law firms to move away from a factory model to one in
Special Issue: Law Firms, Legal Culture, and Legal Practice
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society, Volume 52, 33–71
Copyright r2010 by Emerald Group Publishing Limited
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1108/S1059-4337(2010)0000052005
33
which commitment to clients, not independence from them, is the
organizing principle.
Firms boast of their independence from clients y[y]et virtually from its inception the
large law firm has been attacked for ydiminish[ing] the ability of lawyers to make
informed ethical judgments. (Nelson, 1988, p. 231)
Robert Nelson’s research debunks the independence of corporate law firms
from their clients and the autonomy of lawyers within them to deviate from
their clients’ wishes. As he notes, he joins a long tradition of denying lawyer
independence not only from their clients but also from their firms. And that
tradition has continued unabated (see, e.g., Heinz, Nelson, Sandefur, &
Laumann, 2005).
Despite repeated findings that corporate lawyers arenot independent from
their clients, independence persists among those who ‘‘use and think about’’
(Ewick & Silbey, 1998, p. xi) corporate lawyers and their firms. For example,
economists use the ability to post a reputation for independence as a bond in
order to explain the existence of law firms (see, e.g., Ribstein, 1998). It is part
of legal culture that corporate lawyers and law firms are analyzed, by
researchers at least, through the lens of independence. The fundamental
research question asks whether lawyers can resist client demands and
whether law firms can sustain such independence.
I propose that corporate lawyers and their firms be studied by thinking of
them as committed to their clients and inquiring as to how they handle these
commitments. Instead of asking whether they are really independent, we
should ask how they engage with their clients and their projects. Instead of
presuming that they are neutral toward their clients’ ends, we should presume
that they have chosen interests to promote. Instead of asking whether law
firms have power to escape client control, we should ask how they advance
their clients’ exercises of power.
There are at least four advantages to thinking about corporate lawyers as
committed to their clients. First, such an approach comports better than
independence with the reality of corporate lawyering. Second, it focuses on
organizational goals, in addition to lawyer agency. Third, it can build on the
perspectives and research findings of the cause lawyering project. And
fourth, it politicizes corporate legal practice.
First, thinking of corporate lawyers as committed to theirclients may better
describe practice than thinking about them through the lens of independence
because ‘‘it is unrealistic to think of corporate lawyers as neutral
professionals’’ (Nelson, 1988, p. 249) and ‘‘[t]he notion that lawyers struggle
ROBERT ELI ROSEN34
with their clients over fundamental questions about the common good is
simply wrong’’ (Nelson, 1988, p. 258). Since they are not neutral, examining
the nature of their commitments may be a more fruitful line of research than
examining their independence. Since they do not disagree with their clients’
worldviews, examining their and their clients’ value commitments may be a
more fruitful line of inquiry than examining the fate of independent
professional values. Asking how they elaborate their commitments to clients
may better describe the choices facing corporate lawyers than thinking about
them as attempting to maintain independence from clients.
Second, thinking of corporate lawyers as committed to their clients’
projects emphasizes that lawyers help determine and are determined
by the organizational needs and capacities of their clients. It also emphasizes
that successful law firms are those which adapt to meet client needs.
Thinking through independence: (1) segregates lawyers from clients; (2) the
maintenance of lawyer professional privileges and orientations is the issue;
(3) ethical lawyers have an agenda to impose on their clients; and (4) law
firms are praised for not demanding that their lawyers always supply what
clients demand. Thinking through independence makes suspect the
organizational needs of both clients and law firms. Yet, these needs are
what shape the practice of law:
The needs of the organizations, as perceived and defined by the organizations, shape
lawyers’ careers, direct their work, and influence their prospects for success – financially,
professionally, and perhaps even in their personal lives. (Heinz et al., 2005, p. 320)
Rather than asking whether lawyers can withstand the needs of their
clients and firms, thinking through lawyer commitments asks how they
are organized to serve their clients. We can examine the ways in which
law firms and corporations organizationally map onto each other, shaping
what is demanded from lawyers and how what lawyers supply is received.
We can treat the firm and the corporation as partner organizations, enabling
a view of how power flows between them and how their interests are jointly
determined.
Third, thinking through corporate lawyers as committed to their clients
allows the use of perspectives that have been so useful in describing ‘‘cause
lawyers’’ (see Sarat & Scheingold, 1998, for an introduction). Research on
‘‘cause lawyers’’ has examined the fate of commitments in lawyering. It has
elaborated ways in which lawyer projects may differ from client projects.
It has elaborated ways in which lawyers and legal organizations influence
client agenda and vice versa. It emphasizes client projects, not legal services,
but studies both in their relations to power. Researchers who think through
Rejecting the Culture of Independence 35

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT