Reconsidering Positivity Theory: What Roles do Politicization, Ideological Disagreement, and Legal Realism Play in Shaping U.S. Supreme Court Legitimacy?

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jels.12157
AuthorJames L. Gibson,Michael J. Nelson
Published date01 September 2017
Date01 September 2017
Reconsidering Positivity Theory: What
Roles do Politicization, Ideological
Disagreement, and Legal Realism
Play in Shaping U.S. Supreme
Court Legitimacy?
James L. Gibson* and Michael J. Nelson
To what degree is the legitimacy of the U.S. Supreme Court currently at risk? Perhaps the
most widely accepted view of how the Supreme Court acquires and maintains its legitimacy
is positivity theory, which claims that the legitimizing symbols of judicial authority protect
the Court’s legitimacy from dissatisfaction with its rulings. Although research has shown
that belief in legal realism does not itself threaten the Court’s legitimacy, positivity theory
suggests that portrayals of the Court as embroiled in politics---that is, as “just another
political institution”---can undermine institutional legitimacy. Still, some recent research
recognizes that ideological disagreement poses a serious threat to the legitimacy of the
Supreme Court. Missing from extant literature is a reconciliation of how these three
determinants---ideological dissatisfaction, legal realism, and perceptions of judicial
politicization---combine to structure judicial legitimacy. Understanding the difference
between perceptions of an “ideological” Court versus a “politicized” Court for institutional
legitimacy is our central purpose in this article. We discover that the greatest threats to the
Court’s legitimacy lie in beliefs that judges are just ordinary politicians (not in ideological
dissatisfaction or legal realism). We conclude by drawing out these findings’ implications
for the upcoming highly politicized battles over nominations to the high bench.
*Address correspondence to James L. Gibson, Department of Political Science, Washington University in St.
Louis, Campus Box 1063, St. Louis, MO 63130-4899; email: jgibson@wustl.edu. Gibson is Sidney W. Souers
Professor of Government, Washington University in St. Louis, Professor Extraordinary in Political Science,
Stellenbosch University, South Africa, and a Fellow at the Centre for Comparative and International Politics;
Nelson is Jeffrey L. Hyde and Sharon D. Hyde and Political Science Board of Visitors Early Career Professor in
Political Science and Affiliate Law Faculty, The Pennsylvania State University.
This is a revised version of a paper delivered at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Associa-
tion, San Francisco, CA, September 3–6, 2015. We greatly appreciate the support of Steve Smith and the Weiden-
baum Center for this research. We also acknowledge the assistance of Patrick Tucker in preparing these data for
analysis, and we appreciate the comments of Pamela Corley, Deborah Beim, Markus Neumann, Jeffrey Ziegler,
Miguel Maria Pereira, and Dan Sikorsky on an earlier version of this article.
592
Journal of Empirical Legal Studies
Volume 14, Issue 3, 592–617, September 2017
I. Introduction
In recent years, scholars have devoted a great deal of new attention to assessing the
legitimacy of the U.S. Supreme Court. This interest reflects the realization that legiti-
macy is an invaluable form of political capital for the institution, an asset that often con-
tributes to the solution of the Court’s inexorable “countermajoritarian dilemma.”
1
If the
Court can add to the proportion of the population pleased by its decisions a sizable
additional proportion who, while displeased, will accept the Court’s decisions as legiti-
mate, the justices can continue to be emboldened to perform their minoritarian role in
the U.S. political process. It is no wonder, therefore, that the justices often fret about
the need for maintaining their institution’s legitimacy.
2
One of the most important theoretical innovations of this new spurt of activity is
the positivity theory of Gibson and his colleagues (e.g., Gibson & Caldeira 2009). Positiv-
ity theory accounts for the venerable finding that to know more about the Court is to
“love” it more. That is, exposure to the institution, even in the context of learning of a
ruling with which one disagrees, seems to enhance the Court’s legitimacy (Gibson et al.
2014). Generally, positivity theory has made considerable inroads among judicial schol-
ars who are regularly exploring the theory (e.g., Bartels et al. 2015; Zilis 2015).
One of the most important implications of positivity theory is the claim that the
Supreme Court is to some degree shielded from its constituents’ displeasure with its deci-
sions. Positivity theory suggests that as citizens pay attention to the Supreme Court, they
learn about its activities, including about decisions with which they might disagree, but they
are also simultaneously exposed to legitimizing symbols (e.g., judges’ black robes) that tend
to create a presumption that, even if the outcome is undesirable, the process of decision
making is fair, and therefore an obligation to accept the decision is created. Because expo-
sure to judicial symbols is not necessarily registered consciously, it is hard for citizens to
rebut its implications, as they might via counterarguing in more conscious information
processing (as in motivated reasoning; see Lodge & Taber 2013). Simply put, the role of
the symbols is to mitigate the negative consequences for the institution of decisions that
run counter to a citizen’s policy preferences (thereby resolving at least a portion of the
countermajoritarian dilemma).
3
Therefore, positivity theory predicts that disagreement with
the Court’s rulings will have limited consequences for the legitimacy of the institution.
1
We invoke the literature on the so-called countermajoritarian dilemma only loosely and with full recognition of
the many nuances and debates that exist in the literature. For illustrations, see Pildes (2010) and Hall and Ura
(2015).
2
The most obvious example is the opinion of Justices O’Connor, Souter, and Kennedy in Planned Parenthood v.
Casey, in which legitimacy plays a prominent role (1992, e.g., 865--66). However, the Casey example is not unique.
Farganis (2012:207) reports that “since the Court’s 1954 decision in Brown, in fact, the justices have made
seventy-one such references to the Court’s institutional legitimacy, compared with just nine in the 164 years up
to that point.”
3
Indeed, one of the most important findings of the work by Gibson et al. (2014) on the effects of judicial symbols
is that, in the presence of the symbols, the delegitimizing effects of disappointment in the Court’s rulings are
reduced to zero (in contrast to fairly strong negative effects when the symbols are not present).
593Reconsidering Positivity Theory

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT