Reconciling Emotion and Rational Choice: Negativistic Auto Theft, Consequence Irrelevance, and the Seduction of Destruction

Published date01 November 2019
Date01 November 2019
DOI10.1177/0022427819828793
Subject MatterArticles
Article
Reconciling Emotion
and Rational Choice:
Negativistic Auto
Theft, Consequence
Irrelevance, and the
Seduction of Destruction
Bruce A. Jacobs
1
and Michael Cherbonneau
2
Abstract
Objectives: We explore negativism in the context of auto theft and examine
its broader phenomenological significance for Rational Choice Theory.
Methods: Data were drawn from qualitative, in-depth interviews with 35
active auto thieves operating out of a large Midwestern U.S. city. Results:
Negativistic offending is malicious, spiteful, and/or destructive conduct
whose purpose is typically more hedonic (i.e., short-term gratification) than
instrumental (i.e., resource-generating) or normative (i.e., moralistic). It is
made possible by the notion of ownership without responsibility: Offenders
controlled a vehicle that was not theirs, promoting consequence irrelevance
which in turn unleashed reckless conduct. Conclusions: Consequence
1
Program in Criminology, School of Economic, Political and Policy Sciences, University of
Texas at Dallas, Richardson, TX, USA
2
Department of Criminology and Criminal Justice, University of North Florida, Jacksonville,
FL, USA
Corresponding Author:
Michael Cherbonneau, Department of Criminology and Criminal Justice, University of North
Florida, 1 UNF Drive, Jacksonville, FL 32224, USA.
Email: m.cherbonneau@unf.edu
Journal of Research in Crime and
Delinquency
2019, Vol. 56(6) 783-815
ªThe Author(s) 2019
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/0022427819828793
journals.sagepub.com/home/jrc
irrelevance clarifies negativism’s logic and permits linkage between affect-
based and rational choice decision-making models.
Keywords
rational choice theory, emotions, decision-making, negativism, motor
vehicle theft
Few theories have been more central to deconstructing the black box of
offender decision-making than Rational Choice Theory (RCT). Tested vig-
orously over many decades on crimes of virtually all types (see, e.g., Cor-
nish and Clarke 1986; Loughran et al. 2016; Matsueda, Kreager, and
Huizinga 2006; Nagin and Paternoster 1993; Piliavin et al. 1986), RCT is
simple and relatively straightforward: Would-be offenders weigh the risks
and benefits of offending and engage in rule breaking when the latter
exceeds the former. Research in this tradition depicts offenders as reason-
ably contemplative and, in some cases, quite calculative during the
decision-making process.
Historically absent from this perspective are emotions. Indeed, the
expected utility model (Becker 1968) that dominates the field h as long
“sought to expunge the utility construct of its emotional content” (Loewen-
stein 2000:426), for two reasons. First, the influence of visceral factors “is
perceived as transient and hence unimportant.” Second, visceral factors “are
seen as too unpredictable and complex to be amenable to formal modeling”
(Loewenstein 2000:431).
Emerging studies suggest that this circumscribed view of offenders’
decision-making terrain may be unduly restrictive. These studies reveal that
emotion has utility in its own right and “tha t the anticipated emotional
consequences of criminal conduct is [sic] one of the benefits or utilities
(“thrills”) that are weighed in th e process of rational decision mak ing”
(Bouffard, Exum, and Paternoster 2000:162). In this article, we expand this
important line of inquiry, examining the way in which affect-driven conduct
can coexist with and even promote behavior, that is, on its face, instrumen-
tal or normative in nature.
1
Using the negativistic conduct of auto thieves as our empirical vessel, we
connect the phenomenology of wanton destruction to the rationality of
offender decision-making. Central to this linkage is the concept of conse-
quence irrelevance. Consequence irrelevance flows from what auto theft
uniquely, though not exclusively,
2
provides: control without ownership.
784 Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 56(6)
Control without ownership (of an object, in this case, a vehicle) removes
responsibility for that object but bestows absolute jurisdiction over its dis-
position in function and practice. This sleight of hand ignites insouciance.
That insouciance, in turn, opens up a phenomenological source of reinfor-
cement, reveals that source to be an alternative form of utility, and infuses
rational choice with the affect-based relevance that it currently lacks. Here-
tofore, analysts have suggested that consequence irrelevance triggers crime
on the front end of offending, owing to powerful emotive forces like rage
and desperation that encourage offenders to do whatever they want and
simply not care. In this article, we focus on consequence irrelevance on the
back end of crime—long after the offense has begun but while it is still
underway—to link phenomenology and rational choice in a conceptually
novel way.
Emotions and Decision-making
Ethnographers (Katz 1988; Wright and Decker 1994) have long highlighted
the phenomenological allure of crime, most of which flows from the sense
of thrill or excitement of doing something forbidden (see also Lofland
[1969] on “adventurous deviance”). Crime can be exhilarat ing, offering
undeniable pleasure borne from taking chances and living on the edge
(Lyng 1990). This capacity has been reported in studies of everything from
graffiti tagging and petty delinquency to shoplifting, fleeing from police,
and drug robbery (see, e.g., Cromwell, Parker, and Mobley 1999; Halsey
2008; Jacobs 2000; Lopez 2008; Sanders 2005). The emergence of trans-
cendence theory in the late 1980s (Katz 1988) and more recent affect-based
models (Loewenstein 1996; Loewenstein, Nagin, and Paternoster 1997; van
Gelder 2013) reveal the increasing recognition that visceral states play a
prominent role in crime’s etiology. Paradoxically, the emotional rewards
from crime must compete with the emotional risks such as fear, anxiety,
guilt, shame, embarrassment, and regret (see, e.g., Hochstetler and Copes
2003; Jacobs and Cherbonneau 2017; Pickett, Roche, and Pogarsky 2018;
Warr 2016). As Bouffard et al. (2000:168) illustrate, “emotional states can
just as likely be felt as uncomfortable or anxiety provoking rather than as
pleasurable ...It is not at all unreasonable to think that, just as they can
facilitate some crimes, strong emotional states felt by offenders can act as a
deterrent and inhibit other crimes.” Indeed, part of the reason that some
crimes are so rewarding is because offenders have to overcome fears and
anxieties that deter the less intrepid, which bestows a palpable sense of
accomplishment (Jacobs and Cherbonneau 2017).
Jacobs and Cherbonneau 785

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT