Reading “History, Rhetoric, Law”

Date01 June 1997
DOI10.1177/0003603X9704200205
Published date01 June 1997
AuthorWilliam J. Curran
Subject MatterSymposium: Provocations and Reflections upon Competition Policy in America
The Antitrust Bulletin/Summer 1997
Reading
"history, rhetoric, law"
BY WILLIAM J. CURRAN III*
439
Professor Rudolph J. R. Peritz concludes his Competition Policy
in America
1888-1992
optimistically, yet his
hope
for democ-
racy's
"continuing possibility"! sounds little different from
our
Founders' dreams.
The dreams scholars share, besides democracy, like liberty and
freedom, or to which scholars succumb, like law and policy, or in
which most believe, like objectivity and reason, need not afflict
us. We can detach our reading from controlling myth, from
belief
in the critical discernment and rational judgment
of
the most per-
ceptive of scholars, and read historical explications like Professor
Peritz's, understanding that no matter their brilliance, they must
serve values, like democracy, that society prizes, and that scholars
admire, regardless of policy roles they might actually play.
How a myth like "democracy," and
our
Founders' fondness for
it, captured anation, along with generations of historians, what-
ever
interpretive skill or rhetorical
technique
they might com-
mand, remains one
of
legal history's least told stories.
*Member of the Nebraska, New York, and Pennsylvania bars.
See R.J.R. PERITZ, COMPETITION POLICY IN AMERICA
1888-1992,303
(1996).
©1997 by Federa! Legal Publications. Inc.
440
The antitrust bulletin
I.
The story begins more than a 100 years before the Sherman
Act's 1890 enactment.
At the Constitutional Convention, George
Ill's
lurking pres-
ence forced the Founders into a seemingly plausible, apparently
rational,
branching
of
power,
competitively
checked
and
bal-
anced,
but
publicly
unaccountable.?
The
power
our
Founders
feared, even if cleaved, checked, and balanced, since not account-
able,
was
to make
democracy
and its
"continuing
possibility"
difficult, as history attests.'
Remarkably,
it was to be
only
a few
years,
following
the
Convention,
before
one
of
our
Founders,
Thomas
Jefferson,
America's ardent democrat, fearing ineffectively checked power,
defected from separation of powers theory, and instead proposed a
pure
democratic
version,
with
branches
neither
competitively
checked nor balanced, but with each branch independent, and sub-
ordinated to the people's true sovereign power.'
If
Jefferson
would
reconstruct
democracy
out
of
a
pure
sovereign will popularly determined, it was his contemporary, and
fellow
political
theorist,
John
Taylor,"
who
would
have
built
democracy upon a single principle of morality, not as the "aristo-
cratic" Adams and his companion Federalists had cleaved democ-
See
M.J.C.
VILE,
CONSTITUTIONAUSM AND THE SEPARATION OF
Pow-
ERS
ch.
VI,
119-75 (1967).
For
the
"history"
of
the
separation
of
powers
doctrine,
see
VILE,
supra
note
2; W. BONOY, SEPARATION OF GOVERNMENTAL POWERS: IN
HIS-
TORY, IN THEORY, AND IN THE CONSTITUTION (1967);
P.K.
CONKIN,
SELF-EVI-
DENT TRUTHS: BEING ADISCOURSE ON THE ORIGINS AND DEVELOPMENT OF THE
FIRST
PRINCIPLES OF AMERICAN
GOVERNMENT-POPULAR
SOVEREIGNTY,
NAT-
URAL RIGHTS, AND BALANCE AND SEPARATION OF POWERS (1974);
Sharp,
The
Classical American Doctrine
of
"The Separation
of
Powers," 2 U.
CHI.
L.
REV.
385 (1935).
See
VILE,
supra
note
2,
at
164-67.
Id.
at
167. See
J.
TAYLOR,
AN
INQUIRY INTO THE PRINCIPLES AND
POL-
ICY OF THE GOVERNMENT OF THE UNITED STATES (1814).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT