A pure hedonic theory of utility and status: Unhappy but efficient invidious comparisons

Published date01 August 2019
Date01 August 2019
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12364
AuthorPascal Courty,Merwan Engineer
Received: 13 July 2018
|
Revised: 3 December 2018
|
Accepted: 18 January 2019
DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12364
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
A pure hedonic theory of utility and status:
Unhappy but efficient invidious comparisons
Pascal Courty
|
Merwan Engineer
Department of Economics, University of
Victoria, Victoria, Canada
Correspondence
Merwan Engineer, Department of Economics,
Business and Economics Building, University
of Victoria, Victoria, British Columbia,
Canada, V8W 2Y2.
Email: menginee@uvic.ca
Funding information
Social Science and Humanities Research
Council (Canada), Grant/Award Number:
SSHRC grant 41021001256
Abstract
We examine status preferences where agents compare their
own utility relative to the utilities of others. As long as
status utility comparisons are not too intense, they do not
affect either the competitive equilibrium or the set of
efficient allocations. However, status utility comparison may
substantially reduce average utility and dramatically in-
crease utility inequality. Equating utility with happiness
operationalizes the theory and provides an explanation of
why invidious comparisons can generate so much unhappi-
ness without much inefficiency. Our theory has very
different welfare implications from other status theories,
even when reduced form representations appear observa-
tionally equivalent.
Our envy always lasts longer than the happiness of those we envy.
La Rochefoucauld (1678/1827)
Apart from economic payoffs, social status seems to be the most important incentive and motivating force
of social behavior.
Harsanyi (1976, p. 204)
1
|
INTRODUCTION
There is now a substantial body of economic theory and empirical studies that incorporate interpersonal
comparisons into economic models. This literature typically locates the status preference on a single variable, such
as leisure (Veblen, 1899/1953), consumption income (Duesenberry, 1949), or positional goods (Hirsch, 1976). Such
status preferences, where relative comparisons are made for a subset of variables in the utility function, generate
allocation distortions that reduce welfare. Layard (1980) and Frank (1985) have long urged us to accept the sad
J Public Econ Theory. 2019;21:601621. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jpet © 2019 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.
|
601
reality that relative comparisons impose major negative externalities that, like pollution, could be taxed to public
benefit.
1
This paper proposes an alternative theory of status preferences that have very different welfare and policy
implications. Our theory is grounded on a hedonic foundation where the status function involves comparisons of
cardinal utilities across individuals. We name this class of status function status utilitybecause utilities are
compared instead of leisure, income, or consumption as is done in the literature. Status utility captures how well an
individual is doing in utility terms relative to their reference group. For statusconscious individuals, where
maximizing own utility is their end goal, utility comparison is the ultimate basis for comparing individuals. Equating
cardinal utility with measures of happiness from the subjective wellbeing (SWB) literature operationalizes the
theory. Happier people have higher status and are happier for it.
In the model, each agents utility is a function of their primary utility and their status utility. Primary utility is the
standard cardinal utility function defined on consumption goods, leisure, and so on. Status utility is a linear function
of the difference between own utility and the weighted sum of utilities of other agents in the reference group. The
utility functions are, therefore, implicit functions of each other. With this system, and assuming status comparisons
are not too intense, we derive the following key results: (a) Utility can be expressed as a function of the primary
utilities of all agents. (b) The set of Paretoefficient allocations is unaffected by the introduction of status utility, and
the competitive equilibrium is unaffected by status utility. (c) Status utility can help explain what appear to be
positional concerns over goods without resort to positional preferences over goods. (d) Status utility generates
network effects that typically magnify utility inequality. (e) In the most relevant cases, status utility is negative sum
and equity policy increases average utility. (f) Utilitarian allocations reduce negative status externalities by
allocating more to those who compare themselves more intensely to others.
Including relative utility comparisons into the standard model need not alter key positive and normative results.
The utility equivalence result (a) boils down to each agents utility ultimately depending positively on their own
primary utility, and the efficiency and equilibrium results (b) depend on not being able to manipulate others
primary utilities.
2
In contrast, the status literature departs from the standard model by incorporating status goods,
where a subset of goods, termed positional goods by Hirsch (1976), generate negative consumption externalities.
The more positional the good, the greater the externality and distortion. To this conclusion, Arrow and Dasgupta
(2009) provide a major qualification. They show that if all goods are equally positional, then the externalities cancel
out.
3
In their economy, each good is separable in the utility function and there is a negative externality from the
absolute level of average consumption of each good. The market equilibrium has no allocation distortions when
good externalities are proportionally symmetric across consumption goods. In our model, the balance is naturally
struck as agents in effect maximize primary utility. Allocations and primary utilities are the same as in the standard
model. This neutrality result survives recursive utility comparisons and all specifications of reference groups.
Our model offers other contrasting perspectives to the literature. Solnick and Hemenway (1998, 2005) and
others find dramatic survey evidence for positional concerns. For example, about half of those surveyed prefer a
world where they get a lower absolute income when it improves their relative income position. However, for
vacations only a few respondents choose less vacation time. The result that income is far more positional than
leisure in the utility function is at odds with the requirement of Arrow and Dasgupta (2009) that goods be equally
positional for externalities to cancel out. In contrast, we show that the survey evidence is consistent with standard
1
Clark, Frijters, and Shields (2008) review the empirical and theoretical literature. Easterlin (1974, 2013) argues that relative comparisons are a key
culprit that explain his controversial claim that income growth has not improved the human lot in developed nations. Consideration of relative
consumption can dramatically alter optimal tax policy (e.g., Aronsson & JohanssonStenman, 2018; Slack & Ulph, 2018).
2
We relate our utility equivalence results to the work of Bergstrom (1999) on interdependent nonpaternalistic altruistic preferences in Section 2.2, and in
Section 3.1, we relate our neutrality results to the general analysis of otherregarding preferences in Dufwenberg, Heidhues, Kirchsteiger, Riedel, and
Sobel (2011).
3
Layard (1980) briefly discusses offsetting externalities. For recent work on offsetting externalities, see Aronsson and JohanssonStenman (2013) and
JohanssonStenman and Sterner (2015).
602
|
COURTY AND ENGINEER

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT