Public goods and public bads

AuthorRichard Cornes,Wolfgang Buchholz,Dirk Rübbelke
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12298
Published date01 August 2018
Date01 August 2018
Received: 3 May2017 Revised: 13 November2017 Accepted: 15 March 2018
DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12298
ARTICLE
Public goods and public bads
Wolfgang Buchholz1Richard Cornes2Dirk Rübbelke3
1UniversitätRegensburg and CESifo Munich,
Germany
2AustralianNational University Canberra, Aus-
tralia
3TechnischeUniversität Bergakademie Freiberg,
Germany
Thispaper is a revised and considerably
extendedversion of Cornes and Rübbelke (2012)
thenentitled “On the Private Provision of Con-
tentiousPublic Characteristics.”
Theauthors want to thank two referees, the par-
ticipantsof the conference “Global Environmen-
talChallenges—From International Negotiations
toLocal Implications” at the ZEW Mannheim in
October2016, especially Todd Sandler,and Anja
Brummeand Michael Eichenseer for their very
helpfulcomments.
In many empirically relevant situations agents in different groups
are affected by the provision of a public characteristic in divergent
ways. Whereas for one group it represents a public good, it is a pub-
lic bad for another group. Applying Cornes and Hartley's aggrega-
tive game approach, we analyze a general model in which such
contentious public characteristics are present and are provided
cooperatively. In particular, we establish neutrality results with
respect to redistribution and growth of income, infer the effects of
preference changes and coalition formation, and present a technol-
ogy paradox. Finally, we compare the outcome of voluntary provi-
sion of the contentious public characteristic with the Pareto-optimal
solution, highlighting a potential conflict between equity and effi-
ciency in this case.
1INTRODUCTION
It is a common phenomenon that members of different groups are simultaneously affected by some economic activity
but have opposing preferences concerning its consequences. Climate protection is usually considered to be a global
public good whose provision is beneficial for all countries in the world. This conceptualization, however,ignores that
global warming—within some limits and apart from catastrophic outcomes producing grave losses for all countries—
might be welfare-improving for some regions and countries. Countries likeCanada or Russia may benefit from a higher
temperature, for example, through reduced heating costs, increased agricultural output, and improved prospects for
the tourism industry,which implies that climate protection can become a public bad for these countries. Therefore, the
effects of climate policy are “contentious” so that a conflict of interest between the beneficiaries and the victims of
greenhouse gas abatement arises.
In the field of environmental economics, opposing utility effects are not restricted to climate policy.In general, envi-
ronmental policies are disadvantageous for agents who do not share “green preferences” underlying these policies
but yet have to bear part of their cost. Forexample, Bostedt (1999) has observed that, within Sweden, many lovers of
nature consider the Swedish wolf as a public good. For reindeer herders in the North it is a public bad instead since
the wolf preys on the migrating reindeers. One can cite many other examples of animals that are, for one section of
the community,a public good while another group regards their preservation as costly, because theyare predators of
domesticated animals, destroyers of plantations, carriers of diseases or come directly into conflict with human settle-
ments like elephants tramplinginto Indian villages.
Journal of Public Economic Theory.2018;20:525–540. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jpet c
2018 Wiley Periodicals,Inc. 525
526 BUCHHOLZ ET AL.
Contentious public characteristics are also present in many fields outside environmentaleconomics. While charita-
ble giving is regarded as a public good by altruistic donors, it is rejected by others emphasizing its potentially adverse
economic effects. In the context of foreign aid, prominent examples for such a critical attitude toward transfers are
Collier (2007) and Deaton (2013), who are afraid of deterioratingperformance incentives on the part of the recipients
in developing countries, waste of money through bad governance, and corruption of the ruling elites. But also arms
races between enemy countries (see, e.g., Bruce, 1990; Ihori, 2000) or lobbyism in support of opposing political goals
(see, e.g., Ihori & Kameda, 2015) can be interpreted from the perspective of contentious public characteristics.
In the presence of contentious public characteristics, the beneficiaries and the victims often have the possibility to
counteract each other: While the beneficiaries, as “augmenters” of the public characteristic, can increase the level of
the public characteristic (and have an incentive to do so), the victims, as “depleters”of the public characteristic, can
reduce it through countervailing measures. An example of such opposing activities appears in the context of climate
change. Whereas the countries that benefit from a lower global temperature mayabate greenhouse gas emissions, the
countries which are negatively affected by mitigation measures might instead purposefully increase greenhouse gas
emissions or conduct geo-engineering1(for example, through albedo modification) in order to increase global temper-
ature. Other examples are obviouslygiven by arms races and lobbying activities.
In economic theory,the simultaneous occurrence of public characteristics that are beneficial for some and adverse
for others has only been treated in quite specific settings until now (Ihori, 2000; Ihori & Kameda, 2015), that is, by
assuming Cobb–Douglas preferences for the agents involved. Using the ideas of the aggregative game approach as
conceived by Cornes and Hartley (2007), it becomes possible to generalize in a straightforward way some of the
already known results and, more importantly, to infer new effects for contentious characteristics which can be aug-
mented by one group and depleted by another. Such an analysis will be conducted in this paper, whose structure
will be as follows. After presenting the theoretical setting2in Section 2, we describe in Section 3 the noncoopera-
tive Nash equilibria of voluntary provision of the contentious public characteristics. By taking up a central issue in
public good theory, the effects of income changes and income redistribution on these Nash equilibria are analyzed in
Section 4, which in particular leads to some novel neutrality results with respect to increases of income. Extending
some findings of Ihori (2000) and Ihori and Kameda (2015), preference changes and coalition formation then are con-
sidered in Section 5. In Section 6, we establish a paradoxical effect caused by improvementsof the victims’ depleting
technology,which results in utility losses for both the augmenters and the depleters. Some of the effects which arise in
case of contentious public characteristics are illustrated by exampleswith Cobb–Douglas preferences in Section 7. In
Section 8 we describe the Pareto-optimal solutions and compare their welfare properties to those of the Nash equilib-
rium. This also enables us to identify some problems of international cooperation in the presence of contentiousness
of public characteristics. In Section 9 we conclude and hint at some possible extensionof the analysis.
2THE MODEL FRAMEWORK
We assume that there are two groups Iand Jof agents which either benefit or suffer from the aggregate level Gof a
public characteristics PC.
GroupI(o f size m) contains the PC beneficiaries. Each agent iIis characterized by his initial endowment (“income”)
wI
iand his utility function is uI
i(cI
i,G), which is defined for all private consumption levels cI
i0ofagentiand all G0
and has the standard properties, that is, it is twice differentiable, quasi-concave and strictly positive increasing both
in cI
iand G(which indicates that Gis a public good for each agent iI). Then indifference curves in a cI
i-G-diagram are
downward sloping and convex(see Figure 1).
1SeeSandler (2018) for a characterization of different geo-engineering approaches and their game-theoretic analysis.
2Unlikeother recent papers on public good theory (see, e.g., Barbieri & Malueg, 2016; Caplan, 2016; Maldonado & Rodrigues-Neto, 2016), complete certainty
andfull information are assumed in our model.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT