Progressive Textualism

AuthorKevin Tobia, Brian G. Slocum & Victoria Nourse
PositionAssociate Professor of Law, Georgetown University Law Center/Distinguished Professor of Law, University of the Pacific, McGeorge School of Law/Ralph V. Whitworth Professor of Law, Georgetown University Law Center
Pages1437-1493
Progressive Textualism
KEVIN TOBIA*, BRIAN G. SLOCUM**, ANDVICTORIA NOURSE***
Textualism is now the Court’s lingua franca. In response, some have
proposed a progressive textualism,defined by the use of traditional tex-
tualist methods to reach politically progressive results. This Article
explores a different kind of progressive textualism.Rather than starting
with the desired policy outcomepolitically progressive or conservative
we begin from one of modern textualism’s central values: a commitment to
democraticinterpretation. As Justice Barrett argues, this commitment
views textualists as agents of the peoplewho approach language from
the perspective of an ordinary English speaker.Textualists thereby claim
to promote democracy by interpreting law consistently with what it commu-
nicates to the ordinary public. However, recent empirical studies reveal
discrepancies between textualist interpretive commitments and how ordinary
people understand legal texts. These discrepancies call into question claims
that textualists’ methodology is committed to democratic interpretation.
A textualism centered on democratic interpretation would be methodo-
logically more progressive if it centered facts rather than fictions about
how ordinary people interpret language. It would recognize that people
understand legal language in light of linguistic (co)textand (con)
text,and sometimes nonliterally; they often understand ambiguous
terms in law to have legal, not ordinary, meanings; and their understand-
ing of law is informed by its apparent purpose and sometimes by inter-
pretive rules that are conventionally justified on normative grounds. In
contrast, current textualism is often methodologically regressive, crafting
a fictional ordinary personmore closely connected to ideological pol-
icy goals than facts about ordinary language comprehension.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION..................................................... 1439
I. THEORIES OF TEXTUALISM...................................... 1448
A. THE DEFINING PRINCIPLES OF TEXTUALISM . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1448
B. THE PRINCIPLES OF TEXTUALISM IN CONFLICT. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1453
* Associate Professor of Law, Georgetown University Law Center. ©2022, Kevin Tobia, Brian G.
Slocum & Victoria Nourse.
** Distinguished Professor of Law, University of the Pacific, McGeorge School of Law.
*** Ralph V. Whitworth Professor of Law, Georgetown University Law Center. Thanks to The
Georgetown Law Journal for excellent editorial assistance and to Bill Buzbee, Anita Krishnakumar and
students in her Advanced Topics in Statutory Interpretationseminar, Agnes Lee, David Luban, Austin
McComb, and Jesus Rodriguez for their helpful comments.
1437
C. A NEW APPROACH: METHODOLOGICALLY PROGRESSIVE TEXTUALISM 1455
II. TEXTUALISM AND CONTEXT..................................... 1458
A. CHOICE OF TEXT AND CONTEXT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1459
1. Smith v. United States and Sentence-Level Context. . . . . 1461
2. King v. Burwell and Holistic Context . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1464
B. INTERPRETIVE RULES AND NONLITERAL INTERPRETATIONS. . . . . . . . 1465
1. Quantifiers and Nonliteral Meanings. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1467
2. Ali v. Bureau of Prisons and Nonliteral Meanings . . . . . . 1468
3. Existing Canons that Produce Nonliteral Meanings. . . . . 1470
4. McBoyle v. United States and Nonliteral Meanings. . . . . 1471
5. Gender and Number Canons and Nonliteral Meanings . . 1472
III. TEXTUALISM AND BROADER INTERPRETIVE RULES................... 1473
A. ORDINARY VERSUS LEGAL MEANING . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1475
1. The Textualist Version of Ordinary People. . . . . . . . . . . 1477
2. Ordinary People and Legal Meaning. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1478
3. Operationalizing Legal Meaning. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1479
B. PRESUPPOSITIONS AND NORMATIVE VALUES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1480
1. Textualists and Interpretive Canons . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1481
2. Presuppositions and Clear Statement Rules. . . . . . . . . . . 1483
3. Ordinary People and Substantive Canons . . . . . . . . . . . . 1486
IV. TEXTUALISM AND PURPOSIVE INTERPRETATION...................... 1488
CONCLUSION...................................................... 1492
1438 THE GEORGETOWN LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 110:1437
INTRODUCTION
Justice Kagan has rescinded her statement of textualism’s ubiquity: Some years
ago, I remarked that ‘[w]e’re all textualists now.’ . . . It seems I was wrong. The current
Court is textualist only when being so suits it.
1
Today, most judges claim fidelity to
the text’s meaning, but not all succeed. As this Article explains, some self-proclaimed
textualistsignore text when convenient, rely on shoddy interpretive methods, and
cling to fictions about how ordinary people understand language. Textualism sits at the
heart of modern judicial interpretation, especially at the Supreme Court. Between 2005
and 2017, the Roberts Court relied on textor plain meaningarguments in almost
fifty percent of majority or plurality opinions concerning statutory meaning.
2
Ordinaryor publicmeaning is prioritized across both statutory and constitutional
interpretation,
3
at the Supreme Court and within the lower federal courts as well.
4
Even
in legal academia, a majority of professors report that they accept or lean toward textu-
alism in statutory interpretation.
5
While courts increasingly rely on textualist principles
to resolve interpretive disputes,
6
high-profile cases and empirical studies illustrate that a
general commitment to the text does not guarantee uniform results, or e ven a consistent
textualist theory.
7
Against this backdropthat we are all textualists now(or at least
claim to be)the pressing question is: Which kind of textualism?
8
1. Justice Kagan remarked, we’re all textualists now,in Harvard Law School, The 2015 Scalia
Lecture jA Dialogue with Justice Kagan on the Reading of Statutes,Y
OUTUBE, at 08:29 (Nov. 25,
2015), https://youtu.be/dpEtszFT0Tg. This statement depends upon an essential ambiguity: whether one
begins or ends with the text. Kagan’s recent recission comes in West Virginia v. Env’t Prot. Agency, No.
20-1530, slip. op. at 28 (U.S. Feb. 28, 2022) (Kagan, J., dissenting).
2. See Anita S. Krishnakumar, Cracking the Whole Code Rule, 96 N.Y.U. L. REV. 76, 97 tbl.1 (2021)
(referring to cases decided between 2005 and 2017).
3. See William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Victoria F. Nourse, Textual Gerrymandering: The Eclipse of
Republican Government in an Era of Statutory Populism, 96 N.Y.U.L. REV. 1718, 1720 (2021).
4. See David Zaring, The Organization Judge,U.C
HI.L.REV.ONLINE (Sept. 25, 2020), https://
lawreviewblog.uchicago.edu/2020/09/25/zaring-judge/ [https://perma.cc/GL8T-FFBK] (describing the
large cohort of young Trump judicial appointees).
5. See Eric Martı
´nez & Kevin Tobia, What Do Law Professors Believe about Law and the Legal
Academy? An Empirical Inquiry. 44 (Feb. 27, 2022) (unpublished manuscript) (on le with authors).
Note that many of these respondents also accepted another option, such as purposivism, suggesting that
many take themselves to be pluralistic textualists.
6. See John F. Manning, Textualism and Legislative Intent,91V
A.L.REV. 419, 41920 (2005)
(explaining that at the close of the twentieth century ‘textualism’ emerged, producing a rather
significant effect on both judicial behavior and academic writing).
7. Compare Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1743 (2020) (For an employer to
discriminate against employees for being homosexual or transgender, the employer must intentionally
discriminate . . . in part because of sex.), with id. at 1757 (Alito, J., dissenting) (Title VII does not
reach discrimination because of sexual orientation or gender identity.), and id. at 1825 (Kavanaugh, J.,
dissenting) (urging the Court to follow ordinary meaningrather than literal meaning). See generally
Victoria Nourse, United Philosophy-Divided Court: Interpretive Conflict on the Trump Court (Mar. 3,
2022) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with authors) (analyzing the 2020 Term).
8. For examples of literature analyzing new forms of textualism, see generally Victoria Nourse,
Textualism 3.0: Statutory Interpretation After Justice Scalia,70A
LA.L.REV. 667 (2019); Tara Leigh
Grove, Comment, Which Textualism?, 134 HARV.L.REV. 265 (2020); and Kevin Tobia & John
Mikhail, Two Types of Empirical Textualism,86B
ROOK.L.REV. 461 (2021). Textualismis a term
sometimes confused with originalism. Public meaning originalism starts with the constitutional text, but
2022] PROGRESSIVE TEXTUALISM 1439

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT