Popular constitutionalism: The new living constitutionalism

DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(08)00803-X
Published date06 May 2008
Date06 May 2008
Pages73-105
AuthorGeorge Thomas
POPULAR CONSTITUTIONALISM:
THE NEW LIVING
CONSTITUTIONALISM
George Thomas
The new assertion of popular political power and responsibility is not equivalent to the
substitution of democratic absolutism for democratic constitutionalism. Constitution-
alism necessarily remains; but the constitutions are instructed frankly to the people
instead of the people to the constitutions.
– Herbert Croly, Progressive Democracy
We live in peculiar times. Pleas for judicial restraint have become
ubiquitous as both the left and the right accuse the Court for engaging in
judicial activism. And yet they do so, at times, in near oblivion of one
another. Thus Dean Larry Kramer of the Stanford Law School can write:
‘‘Outside the liberal academy and the ever shrinking liberal wing of the
Democratic party, yit may simply be that no one thinks the Rehnquist
Court is doing anything all that wrong’’ (Kramer, 2004, p. 230). But the
conservative journal First Things – to take but one very clear example – had
years earlier organized a symposium on ‘‘The End of Democracy? The
Judicial Usurpation of Politics’’ that criticized the Rehnquist Court for
doing much wrong (First Things, 1996; see also Wolfe, 2004). Many of the
essays did so, moreover, in a manner that could find common cause with
elements of Dean Kramer’s call for popular constitutionalism as he insisted
that the Court ‘‘is ultimately supposed to yield to our judgments about what
the Constitution means and not the reverse’’ (Kramer, 2004, p. 248).
Special Issue: Constitutional Politics in a Conservative Era
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society, Volume 44, 73–105
Copyright r2008 by Emerald Group Publishing Limited
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1016/S1059-4337(08)00803-X
73
Kramer even issued a democratic call to arms: ‘‘The Supreme Court has
made its grab for power. The question is: will we let them get away with it?’’
(p. 249). Kramer’s question echoes Robert Bork’s insistence in First Things
that the Court was becoming our ‘‘judicial oligarchy.’’ It might also find
common cause with a one conservative scholars’ more tempered contempla-
tion of ‘‘constitutional resistance’’ to judicial supremacy (Stoner, 2006), or
another’s lament that more and more the Court was ‘‘removing from the
arena of public deliberation questions that were once thought to be at the
center of our public lives’’ (Wolfe, 2004, p. 4).
The seeming agreement does not end here. Indeed, what is most
remarkable about the new wave of scholarship on popular constitutionalism
is that it is often expressed by left of center scholars who have come to
embrace positions that, only a decade or two ago, were deemed a threat to
the very notion of constitutionalism by many on the left. This suggests that
criticism of judicial supremacy was not a passing fancy aimed at the Warren
Court, but like original meaning, has taken solid root in ways that cannot be
easily characterized as left or right (Thomas, 2008;Balkin, 2006). And yet
left critics of the Court and right critics of the Court, not surprisingly, take
issue with different opinions, with the former focusing on the Rehnquist
Court’s opinions such as United States v. Lopez and the latter on its
opinions in cases such as Planned Parenthood v. Casey, even though they
now do so using a common vocabulary. This tension is indicative of our
current constitutional order.
This chapter explores the discontinuities in the current constitutional
order as both conservatives and liberals insist on ‘‘taking the Constitution
away from the Court.’’ It does so by focusing on the turn to popular
constitutionalism by prominent liberal legal scholars, illustrating how
elements that were most prominently associated with conservatives have
been used to criticize and even hold at bay aspects of a potentially
conservative constitutional vision. In fact, popular constitutionalism shares
many of the features – as do calls for judicial minimalism – that were
expressed in conservative critiques of the Warren Court. Yet left
constitutional scholars have turned to these very features to prop up the
legacy of the Warren Court against its conservative critics. The turn to
popular constitutionalism is a result, I suggest, of popular constitutionalists’
position in ‘‘political time’’ – that is, after Ronald Reagan’s 1980 election
and subsequent conservative electoral victories which sparked a debate
about constitutional fundamentals that shapes our current constitutional
discourse (Skowronek, 1993;Busch, 2006). Not only has the character of
national politics changed, but this has included a change in our
GEORGE THOMAS74
constitutional thought and culture, particularly in the kinds of constitu-
tional arguments that are viably put forward.
While popular constitutionalism is part of a broader scholarly turn in
constitutional theory which has happily gone beyond the Court in
examining the contours of American constitutionalism, popular constitu-
tionalists have drawn on these elements to insist upon the terms of
progressive and New Deal constitutionalism as the equivalent of a ‘‘new’’
Constitution or a foundational ‘‘settlement.’’ If conservatives challenged the
‘‘liberal order’’ of the Warren Court years and the New Deal ‘‘break-
through’’ on some issues, liberals have sought to preserve this order against
what many of them deemed a conservative or ‘‘collaborationist’’ Court
(Tushnet, 2006). But, as the prominent conservative critiques of the Court
indicate, the Rehnquist Court has been ‘‘liberal’’ as often at it has been
‘‘conservative’’ (Wolfe, 2004, pp. 1–3;Nagel, 2001).
1
In fact, arguments
about the Rehnquist Court, and now the Roberts’ Court, are often proxies
for arguments about the continued legitimacy of the New Deal break-
through.
Yet, in defending the New Deal order these scholars have attempted to
merge the Great Society and the Warren Court as natural developments of
the New Deal, which might be best seen as attempts to prop up a fractured
constitutional order, uneasily pushing it in new directions, while holding
conservative constitutional understandings at bay. In a curious inversion, I
argue that left liberal defenders of the New Deal order have already broken
with parts of its legacy, while conservative critics of the Court adhere to
elements of the New Deal breakthrough. To some degree, both liberals and
conservatives remain plagued by the progressive and New Deal preoccupa-
tion with the ‘‘problem’’ of judicial review in a democracy, which has
prevented them from offering a coherent foundation to the Constitution.
2
Given these discontinuities, our constitutional politics cannot be readily
characterized as liberal or conservative. It is not simply that the Court itself
embraces these discontinuities, which may well be why both the left and the
right seek to ‘‘take the Constitution away from the courts’’ at particular
moments. While the Court may reflect the current ‘‘political regime’’
(Tushnet, 2005), such a descriptive understanding does not capture the
particular shape that constitutional arguments – including Supreme Court
opinions – have taken in the wake of the New Deal breakthrough (Keck,
2004, p. 11). Nor does this understanding explain the arguments put
forward by popular constitutionalists
3
in relation to the success of
conservatives in partially altering the constitutional landscape. The
connection between these two is the focus of this chapter.
Popular Constitutionalism: The New Living Constitutionalism 75

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT