Optimal disclosure decisions when there are penalties for nondisclosure

Date01 August 2017
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/1756-2171.12197
AuthorRonald A. Dye
Published date01 August 2017
RAND Journal of Economics
Vol.48, No. 3, Fall 2017
pp. 704–732
Optimal disclosure decisions when there
are penalties for nondisclosure
Ronald A. Dye
We study a seller of an asset who is liable for damages if the seller fails to disclose to buyers an
estimate of the asset’s value he knew prior to the sale. Our results include as either the “damages
multiplier” that determines the size of the damages the seller must pay buyers increases, or as
the probability the seller is caught withholding his estimate from buyers increases, the seller
discloses his estimate less often, and as the precision of the seller’s estimate increases, he sells a
larger fraction of the asset.
1. Introduction
Grossman (1981) and Milgrom (1981) made what was, at the time of publication, the
surprising observation that information asymmetry between buyers and sellers of a product need
not cause any difficultyin the operation of the market for the product, notwithstanding the previous
insights of Akerlof (1970), as long as antifraud statutes are strong enough so that sellers of the
product are confined to making truthful (but costless) disclosures of their private information
about the product. Their key insight, the so-called unravelling result, was that the sellers of better
quality products would have an incentive to make disclosures about their products that could not
be truthfully replicated by sellers of inferior quality products.
Grossman’s and Milgrom’s conclusion gave rise to a quandary, as in practice, information
asymmetry between buyers and sellers sometimes does interfere with markets, with buyers
occasionally being surprised postsale about the realized utility or performance of the products
they buy, and sellers of inferior products sometimes successfully selling products at prices that
would not prevail werebuyers as well informed about their products’ attributes as the sellers are.
This quandary led researchers to study what assumption(s) underlying the Grossman-Milgrom
analyses might be violated in practice that could be responsible for information asymmetry
between buyers and sellers continuing to play a key role in the performance of markets, even
when antifraud statutes prevent sellers from making false claims about their private information.
One key assumption is that buyers know when sellers are withholding information. In the
unravelling result, if buyers know that sellers have private information about their products that
they have not disclosed,then buyers must infer that the only reason the sellers have not disclosed
Northwestern University; rdye@kellogg.northwestern.edu.
I would like to thank the Editor, Kathryn Spier,and two anonymous referees, as well as workshop participants at UCLA
and Carnegie-Mellon University,for comments on a previous draft of the manuscript.
704 C2017, The RAND Corporation.
DYE / 705
their information is that disclosing the information would reduce the product’s selling price. Aware
of this, buyers should adopt a posture of “sophisticated skepticism” (Milgrom and Roberts, 1986)
and revise downward the price they propose to pay for the product until sellers find it in their
self-interest to disclose their information.
The preceding logic does not apply when sellers sometimes have no private information
about their products but the sellers cannot credibly convince buyers of that fact. In that case,
a posture of sophisticated skepticism by buyers is inappropriate, because sellers who make no
disclosure are not necessarily withholding unfavorable information: they may simply have no
information to disclose. However, this possibility opens the door for sellers with sufficiently
unfavorable information to mimic the behavior of sellers who possess no information by making
no disclosure. In short, it allows sellers who receive private, but sufficiently negative, information
about their products in equilibrium to “pool” with sellers who received no information. Dye
(1985), Farrell (1986), Jung and Kwon (1988), Shavell (1994), Hughes and Pae (2004), and
Hughes and Pae (2014), among others, have developed models based on this last observation.
The present article contains a model of a seller’s disclosure decision that preserves the
central features of both the Grossman-Milgrom (GM) and Dye-Farrell (DF), etc., models (a seller
of a product/asset only sometimes privately receives information about the asset’s value; if the
seller discloses his information, that disclosure must be truthful) and then goes beyond the GM
and DF models by determining the consequences of the seller facing a requirement to disclose
his information when he receives it. The “duty to disclose” requirement is imperfectly enforced
by some fact finder (auditor, reporter, investigator, etc.) who sometimes, but not always, detects
when the seller withheld information he received from buyers prior to sale. When the fact finder
detects the seller’s withholding, the seller is obliged to make damages payments to buyers. The
damages payments are taken to be a, possibly fractional, multiple of the buyers’ overpayment for
the asset (called the “damages multiplier” in the following), where the overpayment is defined
as the difference between the amount buyers actually paid for the asset and the (counterfactual)
amount they would have paid for the asset had the seller disclosed his information to them prior
to sale.
Westudy a base model along with three extensions of the base model: in the base model, the
asset being sold is indivisible, the seller cannot takeany action before sale that influences the value
of the asset to buyers, and the probability the seller acquires information is exogenously given. In
the first extension, we endogenize the probability that the seller receives information. This first
extension is motivated bythe obser vationthat there are two distinct ways a seller, confronted with
a duty to disclose his private information, can escape liability: disclose information whenever
he receives information or not acquire information. The base model does not entertain the latter
possibility. In the second extension, the asset continues to be indivisible, but we allow the seller
to enhance the asset’s value to buyers by taking some action (that is unobservable to buyers) prior
to sale. This is a practically important problem, as sellers of used cars, businesses, etc., often face
moral hazard in their use, care, etc., of their assets before passing the assets on to others, and
it is useful in such settings to understand how credible voluntary disclosures can ameliorate the
seller’s presale moral hazard in making these action choices. In the third extension, the seller also
can make some value-enhancing investment in the asset prior to sale (as in the second extension),
but the asset is now taken to be divisible, and so the seller can decide whatfraction of the asset to
retain for himself and what fraction to sell to buyers. This third extension is natural for studying
disclosures in an initial public offering (IPO) context, where the founder of a firm retains a
nontrivial fraction of his firm post the IPO, and is also relevant in the modern “sharing” economy
where the owners of an asset can exploit the fact that they intend to use only a limited portion of
the asset’s capacity, and so they can sell off, or rent, to other parties the portion of the asset they
don’t use.
Weobtain a variety of results concerning the seller’sequilibrium disclosure behavior. Among
these results, at least four stand out. To describe the first result, call the seller’s disclosure decision
nonmyopic (resp., myopic) if he takes into account (resp., ignores) the potential liability he is
C
The RAND Corporation 2017.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT