A New Natural Law Reading of the Constitution

AuthorSantiago Legarre
PositionLL.B., Universidad Católica Argentina; M.St., Oxford; Ph.D., Universidad de Buenos Aires. Professor of Law, Universidad Católica Argentina; Independent Researcher, CONICET (Buenos Aires); Visiting Professor, Notre Dame Law School (Indiana) and Strathmore Law School (Nairobi).
Pages877-905
A New Natural Law Reading of the Constitution
Santiago Legarre*
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Introduction .................................................................................. 877
I. What Natural Law Is Not ............................................................. 879
II. Natural Law for Dummies ............................................................ 885
III. The Constitution in the Light of Natural Law .............................. 892
Conclusion .................................................................................... 903
INTRODUCTION
The title of this Article borrows from the subtitle of one of Ronald
Dworkin’s last books, Freedom’s Law: The Moral Reading of the
Amer ican Constitution.1 This Article argues that the United States
Constitutionor any constitution, for that mattershould be interpreted
“morally,” as Dworkin posits; but, forgoing Dworkin’s company, this
Article argues that the morality used in this interpretative venture, which
he oddly called “interpretive,”2 ought to be natural law morality.
To begin, natural law requires an explanation. To do so, it is useful to
explain first what natural law is not. Given the unending confusions, both
terminological and conceptual, this clarification is virtually necessary, and
is tackled in Part I, which is followed by an overview in Part II of what
Copyright 2018, by SANTIAGO LEGARRE.
* LL.B., Universidad Católica Argentina; M.St., Oxford; Ph.D.,
Universidad de Buenos Aires. Professor of Law, Universidad Católica Argentina;
Independent Researcher, CONICET (Buenos Aires); Visiting Professor, No tre
Dame Law School (Indiana) and Strathmore Law School (Nairobi). Many thanks
to the editors of the Louisiana Law Review and to Hector Legarre (in pace), Paul
Baier, John Baker, Michael Bradley, Patrick Button, Madeline Rose Gillen, Sam
Gregg, Mary Joseph, Dwight King, Pat Martin, Gregory Mitchell, Larry Solum,
Jim Stoner, Lee Strang, and Olivia Zicari Clausen for excellent feedback. This
Article is dedicated to the memory of the late Cheney Joseph, Jr.
1. See RONALD DWORKIN, FREEDOMS LAW: THE MORAL READING OF THE
AMERICAN CONSTITUTION (Oxford Univ. Press 1996).
2. Id. at 12.
878 LOUISIANA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78
natural law means for the purposes of this Article. Guided by the classical
tradition,3 this Part also attempts to clarify how natural law connects to
positive law. In light of the diverse modes of connection between natural
and positive law, Part III argues that natural law can factor into
constitutional interpretation in subtle but significant ways. More
specifically, this Article suggests that natural law has two different levels
of presence in constitutional law. The interpretation of constitutional
norms, this Article argues, is more moral with regard to one of the two
modes of connection and more technical with regard to the other mode.
Finally, this Article offers some conclusions.
Why “new” natural law? Russell Hittinger coined the expression “new
natural law theory” in his 1987 book A Critique of the New Natural Law
Theory.4 He used the term to describe and, indeed, as he hoped,
delegitimize a school of thought that has in Germain Grisez its founder
and architect,5 John Finnis a main builder, and Robert P. George its more
recentand most exuberantvoice.6 But these three scholarsas well as
others who purportedly fall under the related label “new natural lawyers”—
never seemed to like the term “new natural law theory.”7 In an apparent
compromise, Finnis accepted an alternative, not altogether different brand:
the new classical natural law theory.8
3. See infra note 8.
4. RUSSELL HITTINGER, A CRITIQUE OF THE NEW NATURAL LAW THEORY
(Univ. of Notre Dame Press 1987).
5. According to a self-declared member of the “new natural law” crew, “new
natural la w” is “the name given a particular revival and revision of Thomistic
Natural Law theory,” a revision “initiated in the 1960s by Germain Grisez.”
CHRISTOPHER O. TOLLEFSEN, THE WITHERSPOON INST., The New Natura l Law
Theory 1, 4 n.1 (2012), http://www.nlnrac.org/contemporary/new-natural-law-
theory#_ednref1 (last visited Oct. 16, 2017) [https://perma.cc/MG2X-NS2Y] .
6. See ROBERT P. GEORGE, MAKING MEN MORAL (Oxford Univ. Press 1993).
7. After recognizing t hat Finnis’s work with Germain Grisez and Joseph
Boyle in developing the understanding of practical reasoning has come to be
known as the “new” natural law theory, Robert P. George argues, in his o pening
contribution to Finnis’s festschrift, that the expression “new natural law theory”
is problematic. Robert P. George, Intro duction: The Achievement of John Finnis,
in REASON, MORALITY, AND LAW: THE PHILOSOPHY OF JOHN FINNIS 1, 6 n.15
(John Keown & Robert P. George ed s., 2013) [hereinafter REASON, MORALITY,
AND LAW]. Finnis’s own sharp reservations regarding the label also are featured
there. JOHN FINNIS, Reflections and Responses, in REASON, MORALITY, AND LAW,
supra, at 468 n.31.
8. John Finnis, Natura l Law: The Classical Tradition , in THE OXFORD
HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 1, 5 (Jules Coleman &
Scott Shapiro eds., 2002). In 1991, Finnis already had alluded to “the new

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT