Natural Rights, Human Rights, and Libertarianism

Published date01 January 2015
AuthorWalter E. Block
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/ajes.12086
Date01 January 2015
Natural Rights, Human Rights,
and Libertarianism
By WALTER E. BLOCK*
ABSTRACT. The present article is devoted to developing a libertarian
understanding of whether natural rights may or may not underpin
human rights and, if so, how. Libertarianism is first defined in terms
of the nonaggression principle (NAP), in answer to the question
“What is the proper use of force?” This provides a basis for the
libertarian positions on property rights, taxation, and many other
issues, including human rights. Various philosophical rationales for
the NAP are explored, including utilitarianism, religion, and natural
rights. The basis of human rights is then examined. Every ethical
tradition supports the nonaggression principle, which makes it an
ideal candidate for the fundamental basis of human rights. Unfor-
tunately, other traditions expand upon human rights by adding
“positive” rights that ultimately violate the NAP. The conclusion
takes up the application of libertarian principles to three issues,
which could be viewed as human rights questions: discrimination,
abortion, and the “trolley problem.” The last one involves taking
one life to save many others.
***
What relationship do natural rights and human rights have with one
another?1And what would a libertarian analysis of this question
involve? In my attempt to wrestle with this challenge, I shall start off
by defining terms. First we consider libertarianism (section 1), then
natural rights (section 2), and third human rights (section 3). We
conclude in section 4 with a discussion of how libertarianism impacts
discrimination, the trolley problem, and abortion.
*The author is the Harold E. Wirth Eminent Scholar Endowed Chair and Professor of
Economics Joseph A. Butt, S.J. College of Business, Loyola University, New Orleans.
Email: wblock@loyno.edu; Web: <http://www.walterblock.com/>
American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Vol. 74, No. 1 (January, 2015).
DOI: 10.1111/ajes.12086
© 2015 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Inc.
1. Libertarianism
Libertarianism is a very narrow political philosophy. It is exceedingly
narrow, or “thin.” It asks but one question, and gives only one answer.
The rest of this viewpoint consists of implications of its basic premise,
and applications of it to real-world issues and problems. What is the
one question? It is: “What is the proper use of force?” That is, on what
occasions would it be justified for a person to use violence against
another or his legitimately owned property? And the one proper
response? It is this: it is justified only in retaliation against initiatory
aggression, or in response to it, or in defense against it.
Of course, property rights play an important role in the libertarian
philosophy. Without them, we could not determine whether initiatory
violence had occurred or not. For example, we see A removing a
television from B’s house. Is A a thief, and thus guilty of violating the
libertarian nonaggression principle (NAP)? It all depends upon who is
the rightful owner of this electronic device.
For the libertarian, justice in property titles is based on homestead-
ing. According to terms developed by John Locke, Murray Rothbard,
and Hans-Hermann Hoppe,2homesteading constitutes mixing our
labor with previously unowned goods or resources. We start with the
human person: we mix our labor with ourselves, in effect, so we are
self-owners. Thus, murder, rape, slavery, kidnapping, assault, and
battery are crimes against the person, and thus violate our ownership
over ourselves. We also homestead virgin territory, and thus come to
own it, too. We can further trace legitimate property titles to any
voluntary exchange, such as buying, selling, gambling, making gifts,
and bartering. As a result, theft, fraud, and so on are also incompatible
with our ownership of animals and inanimate objects we may own.
Libertarianism does not say anything to the effect: “Thou shall not
violate the NAP.” It only avers that if you do so, you have committed
an illicit act. This is important, and obviates objections against liber-
tarianism that have been launched against it in cases such as pushing
someone out of the way of an onrushing truck, or grabbing someone
about to jump off a bridge to his death. Both cases are NAP violations.
This philosophy does not mandate that people do not engage in such
acts. It only states that such acts are impermissible, and punishable
30 The American Journal of Economics and Sociology
(if the victims or their heirs insist). These are “good” NAP violations,
in that they are intended to save lives, and the perpetrator of them is
obligated to pay a penalty for engaging in them. In stark contrast,
there are other well-intended actions, such as Social Security, the
welfare system, the minimum wage law, and other social policies that
some people think have good effects. The difference is that advocates
of these laws would not accept the notion that they are acting in an
illicit manner or that justice requires they be punished for such acts.
Another distinction is that punching someone in order to save him
from drowning is uncontroversial; no one opposes such acts. Those
legislative acts, in contrast, are highly controversial.
As stated so far, it is the rare person who would object to libertari-
anism. After all, this is the essence of a civilized order. Everyone may
do anything he wants to do, provided he does not threaten, or initiate,
violence against innocent people. The opposite is surely barbaric.
(Having mentioned “good” NAP violations above, we will assume
them away for the remainder of this article.) The average person
would not dream of raping his neighbor, stealing from anyone,
assaulting someone; for him, slavery and kidnapping are totally abhor-
rent, and murder of innocent people is, if anything, even worse. Such
violations of the nonaggression principle, apart from a small percent-
age of criminals who engage in them, are universally condemned, and
virtually all of us refrain from such despicable deeds.
Why, then, is not everyone a libertarian? Why did Ron Paul not
become president of the United States by an overwhelming majority?
Why is it that the Libertarian Party typically garners less than 5 percent
of the vote? One explanation is that this nonaggression principle,
while applied whole-heartedly to our friends, neighbors, relatives, to
anyone on a personal basis, is widely seen as not applicable to
government. When the state is involved, seemingly, all bets are off. No
decent person would even dream of stealing property from other
people in their capacity as individuals. Nor would he join them if a
group of his neighbors agreed to do so. This would be the tyranny of
the majority, and he would reject any such course of action with
alacrity and disgust. But, yet, let the government orchestrate the
identical plan, to tax Peter and give (some of) the proceeds to Paul,
not a peep to the contrary will be heard from our typical “decent”
Natural Rights, Human Rights, and Libertarianism 31

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT