Nation and Responsibility: The King and His Soldiers in Shakespeare’s Henry V

AuthorArlene W. Saxonhouse
Date01 December 2021
DOI10.1177/0090591720982951
Published date01 December 2021
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591720982951
Political Theory
2021, Vol. 49(6) 968 –994
© The Author(s) 2020
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/0090591720982951
journals.sagepub.com/home/ptx
Article
Nation and
Responsibility: The
King and His Soldiers in
Shakespeare’s Henry V
Arlene W. Saxonhouse1
Abstract
Who bears responsibility for the actions of a city or state? Is it the entity
that we sometimes call a nation? Or the individual members of the nation?
Shakespeare’s Henry V includes a brief interchange the night before the battle
at Agincourt that addresses this question. A disguised king and the common
soldiers of his army debate who is responsible for the deaths that will occur
during the forthcoming battle if the war they are fighting is unjust: the king
or his soldiers? Who will be punished on Judgment Day? The interchange
opens up reflections on the challenge of deciding who acts when a state
acts. Henry V is a play that emphasizes the role of the imagination as central
to both stagecraft and the politics of creating a nation. Engaging with the
medieval theory of the “king’s two bodies,” the Henry of Shakespeare’s play
is caught between the desire to be the embodiment of the imagined nation
and yet be his own “natural person” when questions of responsibility for
the actions of the nation emerge. Dependent on the imagination to build a
unified nation of diverse peoples, Henry desires to escape responsibility for
the potentially unjust actions of the nation by focusing on the private actions
of his individual subjects. The play thereby brings questions of responsibility
for the actions of collective bodies founded by the imagination to the fore
and forces us to explore who is responsible when states or nations act.
1Department of Political Science, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI, USA
Corresponding Author:
Arlene W. Saxonhouse, Department of Political Science, University of Michigan, 5700 Haven
Hall, Ann Arbor, MI 48109, USA.
Email: awsaxon@umich.edu
982951PTXXXX10.1177/0090591720982951Political TheorySaxonhouse
research-article2020
Saxonhouse 969
Keywords
responsibility, imagination, Shakespeare, Henry V
From the same also it proceedeth that men cannot distinguish without study
and great understanding, between the one action of many men and many
actions of one multitude; as for example, between one action of all the
senators of Rome in killing Catiline and the many actions of senators in
killing Caesar; and therefore are disposed to take for the action of the people
that which is a multitude of actions done by a multitude of men, led perhaps
by the persuasive one.
—Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, Chapter 11, paragraph 20
I. The Problem
What does it mean to say, as we regularly do, that a state “acts”? Germany
invades Poland, England resists, the United States reduces its nuclear arsenal,
the Athenians acquire an empire in the Mediterranean, the Melians refuse to
submit, the Spartans begin a war to restrain the imperial ambitions of the
Athenians. And so forth. Linguistically, these phrases casually roll off our
tongues. Aristotle, writing in the fourth century BCE and analyzing what it
means to live in a political community, asks in the beginning lines of Book III
of Politics: “What in the world is a city (polis)?” Before turning this into the
question of who is a member of the polis and giving his famous definition of
a citizen as one who shares in decisions and judgments, he ponders the ques-
tion of action: “There are disputes, some arguing that the city performed an
action (tên polin peprachenai), others that it was not the city but the oligarchy
or the tyrant.”1 He thus suggests how any change in the regime of a city might
undermine the simple statement that Germany invaded Poland.2 Aristotle fol-
lows up on this dispute when he does not simply ask his readers to identify
who acts in the unsettling situation when regimes change, but also points to
the problem that “some raise” of “when the city performed an action and
when it did not – for example, at the time when a democracy replaces an
oligarchy or a tyranny . . . some do not want to fulfill [public] agreements on
the ground that it was not the city but the tyrant who entered into them.”3 The
“agreements (ta sumbolaia)”—treaties, debts, and so forth—introduce the
question of justice, of what is owed, into this question of what it means to say
that states or cities act.
Aristotle’s challenge, which he himself never really answers, resounds
through our understanding of the politics and justice of political actions taken
by the collective bodies that we now call states. Not only do we ask who acts,

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT