Moral Error, Power, and Insult

Date01 October 2007
AuthorBurke A. Hendrix
DOI10.1177/0090591707304586
Published date01 October 2007
Subject MatterArticles
550
Political Theory
Volume 35 Number 5
October 2007 550-573
© 2007 Sage Publications
10.1177/0090591707304586
http://ptx.sagepub.com
hosted at
http://online.sagepub.com
Author’s Note: I would like to thank Jason Frank, David Tafler, Margaret Taurere,
Loganathan Krishnan, Duncan Ivison, Alison McQueen, and the editors and reviewers of
Political Theory for their helpful feedback on earlier versions of this essay.
Moral Error,
Power, and Insult
Burke A. Hendrix
Cornell University, Ithaca, New York
Defenders of Aboriginal rights such as James Tully have argued that
members of majority populations should allow Aboriginal peoples to argue
within their own preferred intellectual frameworks in seeking common moral
ground. But how should non-Aboriginal academics react to claims that seem
insufficiently critical or even incoherent? This essay argues that there are two
reasons to be especially wary of attacking such errors given the historical
injustices perpetrated by settler states against Aboriginal peoples. First,
attempts to root out error will often be misplaced, because they will fail to
consider the full range of possible reasons for particular kinds of social
practices. Second, such attempts will often have counterproductive social
effects in disrupting conversations and prolonging Aboriginal alienation.
This essay thus argues that non-Aboriginal academics should be willing to
exercise considerable self-restraint toward apparent intellectual errors,
because such a strategy will be most conducive to realizing justice over the
long term.
Keywords: Aboriginal peoples; cultural rights; historical injustice; moral
error; power
Power and Self-Restraint
How much intellectual self-restraint should we as political philosophers
exhibit toward moral claims that seem to us deeply mistaken, particu-
larly if they are made by vulnerable and historically mistreated minorities?
Many defenders of Aboriginal rights, including James Tully, Duncan Ivison,
Robert Williams Jr., Taiaiake Alfred, and others, argue that members of
settler societies owe Aboriginal peoples a chance to press claims using their
own philosophical frameworks, and that we who are non-Aboriginal must
Hendrix / Moral Error, Power, and Insult 551
listen carefully and respectfully to these views.1We must not simply
demand that they speak in our familiar (and hegemonic) terms and cate-
gories, but also take their claims seriously as independent carriers of value
from which we might learn, or (failing that) which we might at least see as
having equal worth to our own.
Yet what if many Aboriginal claims strike us as insufficiently critical,
morally implausible, or logically incoherent? Should we focus on correct-
ing these errors to make the terms of our agreement or disagreement
clearer, or as a way of showing the other side where they have gone wrong?
Or should we exhibit some self-restraint, and allow claims to go unchal-
lenged even if they seem strange or indefensible? In this essay, I want to
consider two types of arguments for exhibiting substantial self-restraint in
many instances. The first argument invokes the difficulties of good moral
judgment, and focuses on the value of long-term listening for improving
our own moral viewpoints: paradoxically, better thinking may sometimes
depend on deciding to be less exacting. The second argument focuses on
the process of interaction itself, and kinds of behaviors necessary to allow
for the growth of mutual respect—even if we do not always believe
Aboriginal peoples, we must at a minimum abstain from insulting them.
Waldron on Indigeneity
To give this essay a clear anchor, let me begin with an example of a
recurring kind of Aboriginal claim, and then a counterargument from a non-
Aboriginal philosopher. Consider the following from Native Canadian John
Borrows, who argues that Aboriginal peoples have both a right and an
obligation to have greater influence within Canada, apparently because of
their ancestors’ prior occupancy:
Aboriginal peoples must transmit and use their culture in matters beyond
“Aboriginal affairs.” Aboriginal citizenship must be extended to encompass
other people from around the world who have come to live on our land. After
all, it is our country. Aboriginal people have the right, and the legal obliga-
tion of prior citizenship, to participate in its changes.2
Notice the essential claim here: “After all, it is our country.” (The empha-
sis is Borrows’s own.) This is obviously a recurring kind of claim in many
Aboriginal arguments—indeed, the notions of “Aboriginal” and “indige-
nous” themselves seem to entail this kind of “firstness.”3Since Borrows is

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT