Making Black Lives Matter: Properly Valuing the Rights of the Marginalized in Constitutional Torts.

AuthorWhite, Helen E.

AUTHOR. Yale Law School, J.D. 2018. I am grateful and indebted to John Witt for his constant encouragement, mentorship, thoughtful feedback, and generous support from the very start. I also owe a great deal of thanks to Daryl Levinson for his guidance on this Note and on writing interesting scholarship. This Note was strengthened considerably by conversations with Guido Calabresi, Issa Kohler-Hausmann, Daniel Markovits, Lincoln Caplan, and Emily Bazelon, and by the thoughtful feedback I received on early versions from Ashraf Ahmed, James Durling, and Bill Powell. I am also grateful for the many people who engaged with me about the ideas in this piece, with particular thanks to Rachel Chung, Christina Ford, Richard Frohlichstein, Ted Lee, Laura Portuondo, Roseanna Sommers, Harrison Stark, and Emily Wanger for their helpful conversations and support as this piece took shape. Additional thanks to Giovanni Sanchez for his thoughtful comments and editorial suggestions, as well as to Christine Smith, Zoe Jacoby, and all the editors of the Yale Law Journal for their careful editing. All arguments and errors in this Note are my own.

NOTE CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION 1745 I. THE CONSTITUTIONALITY OF RACE-BASED ACTUARIAL TABLES 1752 A. State Action in Private Torts 1753 B. State Action in Constitutional Torts 1757 C. Classifications, Narrow Tailoring, and Compelling State Interests 1762 D. Lingering Concerns About Accuracy 1765 II. CORRECTIVE JUSTICE AND CONSTITUTIONAL TORTS 1766 A. The Origins and Appeal of Corrective Justice 1766 B. The Incomplete Importation of Corrective Justice from Private Tort Law 1768 C. Applying a Broader Transactional Scope Within a Corrective Justice Framework to Actuarial Tables 1772 III. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE AND CONSTITUTIONAL TORTS 1775 A. Distributive Justice as Applied to Constitutional, Rather than Private, Torts 1776 B. Evaluating Supercompensatory Damages for Constitutional Torts in a Distributive Justice Framework 1781 IV. TOWARD A DISTRIBUTIVE CONSTITUTION? TRADE-OFFS AND IMPLICATIONS 1788 INTRODUCTION

On the evening of April 19, 2017, a Texas police officer fired four shots into a vehicle driving away from a high-school party. (1) One of those bullets struck and Killed Jordan Edwards, a fifteen-year-old Black boy who was sitting in the passenger seat. Jordan's parents have since filed a civil rights lawsuit against the officer arguing that the officer used excessive force when he shot Jordan. (2)

Since the 2014 shooting of another young, unarmed black man by a police officer in Ferguson, Missouri, activists have campaigned for a societal recognition that "Black Lives Matter." (3) Scholars and commentators have advocated for new standards for police use of force (4) and brought to light the disproportionate impact of certain police practices on minority communities. (5) Protests have erupted as a series of police officers were acquitted of various forms of criminal homicide, if the officers were ever charged at all. (6) This has led to the common refrain that "Black Lives Matter" and that our criminal justice system must begin to reflect that fact. (7) However, little attention has been paid to the fact that Black lives are systematically undervalued even when governments do compensate victims of police violence. (8)

The literal undervaluation of Black lives is the result of constitutional torts' adoption of a corrective justice approach to calculating damages. More specifically, Black lives are compensated at a discount because courts use race-based actuarial tables to calculate how much defendants must pay plaintiffs. To understand how this works, we must first consider the scheme used to calculate tort damages. (9) When a young person is killed or seriously injured by a tortfeasor, such as a negligent driver, courts rely on actuarial tables to try to calculate damages. The tables help calculate how much the victim would have earned, how long they would have worked, and how long they would have lived. So too when a child is shot by a police officer, in violation of the Fourth Amendment, or denied medical treatment while incarcerated, in violation of the Eighth Amendment.

But these tables are not simply the average expected outcome for a "typical" or "average" person. Rather, the tables show the average member of a group defined not only by such metrics as age and income but also by race. (10) Problematically, this results in lower damages valuations for Black lives since the tables estimate that they will live shorter lives and earn less money. It is shocking enough that tort law relies explicitly on such measures. It is even more startling that our civil rights enforcement mechanisms have adopted tort law's race-based approach to valuing lives.

Consider the example of a fifteen-year-old Black boy, like Jordan Edwards. When an adolescent is killed or seriously injured, estimating damages in a subsequent lawsuit is a major challenge. Little is known about the victim's future educational attainment, health habits, or employment prospects. So, in light of this uncertainty, experts must guess. In doing so, forensic damages experts almost always use two factors to approximate an individual's life expectancy and earnings: sex and race. (11) Jordan would be expected to live another 58.4 years. (12) The average weeldy wage for a Black man in 2016 was $718. (13) Based on these numbers, Jordan's lost earnings would be worth about $2.1 million, without adjusting for future inflation or discounting to present value. If Jordan were white, however, his lost earnings would be just under $3 million. (14) Under our civil rights law, a Black boy's life is worth about seventy percent of a white boy's.

As of early 2019, Jordan's case had yet to be resolved (15) and, like many such lawsuits, is likely to end in settlement. But there is ample evidence that race-based damages calculations in [section] 1983 civil rights cases are common. (16) In one case, an expert witness who had performed thousands of lost-income analyses across his career testified that "no one had ever asked him to provide race- and sex-neutral calculations in wrongful death cases." (17) Even when cases settle, this near-consensus approach to damages calculations informs the parties' initial bargaining positions and, by extension, the ultimate settlement. (18) Therefore, these tables are at the center of how we value the rights and lives of people harmed by others--including victims of unconstitutional state violence.

Yet plaintiffs' lawyers rarely challenge the use of race-based actuarial tables in court. Surprisingly, parties routinely stipulate to their use. (19) Indeed, plaintiffs' lawyers have generally overlooked how race-based tables reduce plaintiffs' recovery amounts, even as they target other factors for that very reason. Consider the following perplexing example: In Estate of Gaither ex rel. Gaither v. District of Columbia, a plaintiff's expert used race to calculate damages in a case alleging unconstitutional conditions of imprisonment. (20) By using tables that undervalue Black lives, the plaintiff's expert considerably reduced the potential award. Yet, at the same time, the plaintiff challenged the defendant's expert's use of the client's socioeconomic status in calculating lost earnings. (21) If the plaintiff's lawyer was concerned about improperly reducing the award amount, why rely on a race-based able in the plaintiff's own report?

Similarly in Woodson v. City of Richmond, another constitutional tort case, the plaintiff's expert objected to the city's use of an online life-expectancy calculator that considered multiple factors not included in the standard actuarial tables, such as diet, exercise, and other lifestyle factors. (22) One of the objections the plaintiff's expert raised was that this calculator was impermissible because it was not sufficiently individualized, in part because it did not consider race. (23) Talcing Woodson and Estate of Gaither together with the widespread practice of stipulating to the use of race-based tables suggests that there is an assumption--even by plaintiffs' lawyers--that race is relevant to calculating constitutional tort damages.

Though the use of race-based tables means Black lives are systematically undervalued, few courts have considered their constitutionality. Indeed, in the constitutional tort context, no court has ever struck down the use of race-based tables on constitutional grounds. And, in nonconstitutional cases, just three courts have struck down their use. (24) But even these courts were primarily squeamish about the reliability of the tables, not their constitutional implications. In short, these courts reasoned that because the defendant had not shown this particular person of color would live a shorter life or earn less money, the race-based figure was not a reliable way to calculate damages. This line of reasoning, however, is as much an argument against actuarial tables and statistical modeling as it is against the use of any particular factor in calculating damages. It does not address the uniquely problematic aspects of race-based tables and their potential equal protection implications.

This Note argues that the acceptance by plaintiffs' lawyers of race-based tables and courts' concerns about accuracy arise out of the same flawed assumption: that the goal of constitutional tort remedies is to restore a plaintiff to the position she was in before the unconstitutional conduct. This Note demonstrates that this seemingly value-neutral, technocratic fashion of calculating damages is anything but. Instead, the very selection of a narrow, private-tort-like framework smuggles in a value judgment that entirely ignores background conditions of inequality. Once the normativity of the current approach is laid bare, competing approaches--such as distributive justice or more historically sensitive corrective justice--that have long been discounted by scholars...

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT