Knowledge-Making in Politics: Expertise in Democracy and Epistocracy
Published date | 01 June 2024 |
DOI | http://doi.org/10.1177/00905917231199495 |
Author | Matthew C. Lucky |
Date | 01 June 2024 |
https://doi.org/10.1177/00905917231199495
Political Theory
2024, Vol. 52(3) 431 –458
© The Author(s) 2023
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/00905917231199495
journals.sagepub.com/home/ptx
Article
Knowledge-Making
in Politics: Expertise
in Democracy and
Epistocracy
Matthew C. Lucky1
Abstract
Recently, epistocrats have challenged the value of democracy by claiming
that policy outcomes can be improved if the electorate were narrowed to
empower only those with sufficient knowledge to inform competent policy
decisions. I argue that by centering on contesting how well regimes employ
extant knowledge in decision-making, this conversation has neglected to
consider how regimes influence the production of knowledge over time.
Science and technology studies scholars have long recognized that political
systems impact the productivity of expert research. I argue that in order to
evaluate which regime is “smarter,” we must consider not only how well
they employ existing knowledge in decision-making, but we must also assess
how those regimes influence the ongoing production of policy-relevant
knowledge. Thus, I offer an instrumental defense of democracy based on its
capacity to encourage a superior pattern and quality of expert research to
inform policy decisions over time. Epistocracy may be effective at employing
extant knowledge in the short run, but in the long run, democracy is a
superior environment for producing knowledge to inform policy decisions.
1Indiana University Bloomington, Bloomington, IN, USA
Corresponding Author:
Matthew C. Lucky, Indiana University Bloomington, Woodburn Hall, 1100 East 7th Street,
Bloomington, IN 47406, USA.
Email: mclucky@iu.edu
1199495PTXXXX10.1177/00905917231199495Political TheoryLucky
research-article2023
432 Political Theory 52(3)
Keywords
epistocracy, epistemic democracy, science and technology studies,
meritocracy, knowledge systems
Contemporary democracies are experiencing a prolonged period of threats
from populist antisystem forces (e.g., Connolly 2017; Levitsky and Ziblatt
2018). Mounk (2018) likewise flags survey evidence of a multidecade decline
in support for belief in the essential value of living in a democracy (105–10).
As democracies degrade and publics grow skeptical of their value, epistocrats
such as Brennan (2017), Somin (2016), Bell (2015), and Caplan (2011) argue
that the best response is to sacrifice democracy in order to save and fortify the
authority of experts over policy decisions. They indite the mass publics in
democracies as incorrigibly ignorant, irrational, and tribalistic. In contrast,
epistemic democrats such as Landemore (2012, 2020), Estlund (2009;
Estlund and Landemore 2018), Surowiecki (2005), and Goodin and
Spiekermann (2018) argue that rule by expert groupthink is prone to failures
of myopic vision. Instead, they argue that democratic decision-making pos-
sesses emergent epistemic properties that epistocrats wrongly discount. Other
committed democrats, such as Bagg (2018) and Achen and Bartels (2017),
lament that the mechanisms for democracy’s alleged emergent epistemic
properties often appear to be fragile beyond restrictive conditions. They con-
tend that a more realistic and robust defense of democracy is possible, though
that defense centers on valuing democracy narrowly as an anticorruption
mechanism after accepting the bulk of epistocratic critiques of voter compe-
tence. Ultimately, I side with the democrats here and offer an epistemic
defense of popular rule. Unlike the existing defenses, however, I do not locate
democracy’s advantages in the emergent properties of collective decision-
making or anticorruption mechanisms. Instead, I argue that democracy is bet-
ter than epistocracy at producing socially useful patterns of expert research.
Advocates for competing regimes agree that we ought to evaluate regimes
on the exclusive basis of their instrumental merits. To wit, we ought to value
regimes based on their ability to solve social problems. Brennan (2017)
claims “the only reason to favor democracy [or epistocracy] over any other
political system is that it is more effective at producing just results” (11). I
reformulate the instrumental criteria of solving social problems here as the
question of which regime is more capable of intelligent action. Intelligent
action, whether it be performed by individuals, political assemblies, AIs, ani-
mals, or regimes, requires the actor(s) to engage with the world with intention
To continue reading
Request your trial