The illegitimacy of one-sided speculation: getting the defensive gun use estimate down.
Jurisdiction | United States |
Author | Kleck, Gary |
Date | 22 June 1997 |
Introduction
It is obvious to us that David Hemenway (H) had no intention of
producing a balanced, intellectually serious assessment of our
estimates of defensive gun use (DGU). Instead, his critique serves the
narrow political purpose of "getting the estimate down," for the sake
of advancing the gun control cause. An honest, scientifically based
critique would have given balanced consideration to flaws that tend to
make the estimate too low (e.g., people concealing DGUs because
they involved unlawful behavior, and our failure to count any DGUs
by adolescents), as well as those that contribute to making them too
high. Equally important, it would have given greatest weight to
relevant empirical evidence, and little or no weight to idle speculation
about possible flaws. H's approach is precisely the
opposite -- one-sided and almost entirely speculative. Readers who have any
doubts about the degree to which H's paper is imbalanced might carry out a
simple exercise to assess our claim -- count the number of lines H
devotes to flaws tending to make the estimate too high and the number
devoted to flaws making the estimate too low. We submit that the
ratio is over 100-to-1, i.e., almost entirely devoted to speculations
about why the estimate is too high.
The political function of this advocacy scholarship is clear. While
high estimates of DGU frequency do not constitute an obstacle to
moderate controls over guns, they constitute the most serious obstacle
to advocacy of gun prohibition. Disarming the mass of noncriminal
prospective crime victims would, if high DGU estimates are even
approximately correct, result in large numbers of foregone
opportunities for uses of guns that could prevent deaths, injuries, and property
loss. To acknowledge high DGU frequency would be to concede the
most significant cost of gun prohibition. H's paper is an attempt to
neutralize concerns about such costs and to provide intellectual
respectability for positions identified with Handgun Control
Incorporated (HCI), the nation's leading gun control advocacy group.
H has close ties to HCI through two key staff members of HCI's
"educational" branch, the Center to Prevent Handgun Violence
(CPHV). His closest and most frequent collaborator on gun-related
research is Douglas Weil, currently Research Director of CPHV,(1) while
H has co-edited a strongly pro-control propaganda tract with Dennis
-
Henigan, legal counsel to HCI and CPHV.(2)
H's political intentions and strong feelings are also evident in his
overstatements and in the grandiose conclusions he draws from weak
or irrelevant evidence and fallacious reasoning. He does not get past
his tide before making his first overstatement, claiming that he had
established, without benefit of any new empirical evidence, that our
estimates are too high and that they are "extreme overestimates."(3)
He states in his first paragraph that "it is clear that [the Kleck and
Gertz] results cannot be accepted as valid."(4) He incorrectly claims
that "all checks for external validity of the Kleck-Gertz finding confirm
that their estimate is highly exaggerated,"(5) when in fact these checks
have repeatedly confirmed our estimates.
DGUs usually involve unlawful possession of a gun by the gun-wielding
victim, and sometimes other illegalities as well,(6) a point H
does not dispute. Yet, in making the extraordinary and
counterintuitive claim that there is a social desirability bias to people
reporting their own illegal behavior,(7) H insists that such a desirability
bias is not only plausible, but that it is likely.(8) By the end, without having
provided a scintilla of credible supporting evidence, H concludes that our
research was afflicted by an "enormous problem of false positives"
(persons claiming a DGU who did not have one) and "massive
overestimation," flatly stating that "the Kleck and Gertz survey results do not
provide reasonable estimates about the total amount of self-defense
gun use in the United States."(9) It is an impressive achievement to be
able to arrive at such high-powered conclusions without the
inconvenience of gathering or even citing any new empirical evidence.
-
The Illegitimacy of One-sided Speculation: An Ounce or Evidence
Outweighs a Ton of Speculation
H's critical technique is simple: one-sided, and often implausible,
speculation about flaws that might have afflicted our research, and
that might have been consequential enough to significantly affect our
conclusions. H devotes his attention almost exclusively to suspected
flaws that might have contributed to the overestimation of defensive
gun use (DGU) frequency. He either ignores well established sources
of underreporting, or briefly and superficially discusses them only for
the sake of dismissing them.(10) When H speculates about sources of
response error that are plausible, he offers no rationale for why the
problems should lead to more false positives than false negatives.
Instead he simply conjures up reasons they might lead to false positives.
As support for his one-sided speculations H even cites other people
guilty of the same dubious practice.(11)
All research is flawed. Known flaws should be identified and
their likely impact assessed. Speculation about flaws can play a role in
the pursuit of truth by motivating researchers to gather better
empirical evidence less afflicted by the flaws. Speculation by itself, however,
should not be given any weight in assessing evidence. An ounce of
evidence, even though flawed, outweighs a ton of speculation.
Unfortunately, in both good research and bad, there is no upper limit on
the amount of speculative criticism that can be directed at the work,
and thus this sort of critique is just as easily applied to good research
as to bad.
-
Red Herrings and the Issue Not Addressed
Much of H's paper is a red herring in that it implicitly misstates
the central technical question about our estimates. Much of it is
devoted to elaborate speculations about why people might falsely claim
to have used a gun defensively, as if it were somehow in dispute that
there are some false positives.(12) He inaccurately hints that we
unreasonably ignored the possibility that some of our respondents (Rs)
provided false positives.(13)
We assume as a matter of course that our survey is like all other
surveys in that some Rs give inaccurate responses to questions, and
that these errors include both false positives and false negatives. The
central question is not whether there are false positives, nor even how
many false positives there are, but rather what the relative balance is
between false positives and false negatives. Because H makes no effort
to assess the frequency of false negatives,(14) it is logically impossible for
him to draw meaningful conclusions about whether our estimates
were too high or low.
-
The Nature of False Positives
It is hard to discern exactly what kinds of false positives H thinks
most often show up in all these gun use surveys. He waffles on the
issue of whether people are: (1) consciously inventing nonexistent
events; (2) consciously but honestly misrepresenting accounts of real
events that did not really involve DGU (e.g., they involved aggressive
use of a gun); or (3) unconsciously distorting real events. He seems to
have doubts himself about possibility (1) occurring very often,
hastening to assure readers that false responders do not necessarily have to
lie,(15) but is otherwise unwilling to commit himself to the relative
frequency of these types of misreports.
It is worth emphasizing how difficult it was for our Rs to falsely
report a completely nonexistent event as a DGU. Unlike the UFO
example that H insists is somehow parallel to reports of DGUs,(16) a
respondent who wanted to falsely report a nonexistent DGU could not
qualify as having had such an experience merely by saying "Yes."
Rather, respondents had to provide as many as nineteen internally
consistent responses covering the details of the alleged incident. In
short, to sustain a false DGU claim, Rs had to do a good deal of agile
mental work, and stay on the phone even longer. On the other hand,
all it took to yield a false negative was for a DGU-involved R to speak a
single inaccurate syllable: "No." The point is not that false positives
were impossible, but rather that it was far harder to provide a false
positive than a false negative.
Consider also the context in which H imagines all these false
reports to have occurred. Randomly selected people were called
unexpectedly, and questioned rapidly by total strangers, for no more than
fifteen minutes, with one question immediately following another.
There was no prolonged opportunity to invent a nonexistent event,
rehearse inaccurate details, or to otherwise get an false story straight.
Rs providing a false positive had to be not only dishonest but very
quick-witted as well.
Regarding possibility (2), we noted that most of the DGUs were
linked with the types of crimes -- burglaries, robberies, and sexual
assaults -- where there is little opportunity for participants to be honestly
confused about who was the victim and who was the offender.(17) While
a few Rs may well have consciously misrepresented aggressive actions
as defensive, and a very few might have consciously invented entirely
fictitious events, it is hard to see how Rs could report an account of a
real burglary, robbery, or sexual assault in which they were aggressors
and somehow honestly distort it into a DGU incident.
This kind of misunderstanding of real events in a way that falsely
qualifies them as DGUs is more plausible in connection with
male-against-male assault incidents, such as when people prefer to
characterize their partly aggressive, partly defensive behavior in "mutual
combat" incidents as purely defensive in character. We addressed this
latter possibility in our article and showed that it could not account
for more than a small fraction (probably less than a tenth) of the
incidents...
To continue reading
Request your trialCOPYRIGHT GALE, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.